Why it is your duty to stop supporting the government →
ethics →
are ethics just aesthetics, instincts, lifecycle trends, or fashion statements?
A devil’s advocate psychoanalyzed me while I was away in Guatemala :
A few months back he found God, or his atheist non-existent equivalent.
His emails to me began to change — at first I noticed the enthusiasm and purposefulness and figured he was just remembering how fun life can be if you’re not dragging a heavy desk job around on your back (he quit his job during his miracle conversion).
But I also noticed a change of tone that seemed familiar but that I couldn’t quite place.
Then I realized… that he was acting born-again.
It was not at all what I would have expected from the old cynic…
The obsession with questions of ethics (which he’d always seemed to dismiss as a dead-end street before); the cosmic portent he attributed to mundane choices in his wee, mortal, primate life; the way his words seemed to survey the field from a high altitude… everything was there except the wrathful thunder-voice from the clouds telling him what to do and the surrender to a mildewed literature of mythology and dogma.
Or so I hoped.… I’d tried to draw him out in email and get him to admit that he’d signed up for Landmark or gone in for that Buddhist stuff again or joined Narcotics Anonymous in the middle of a bad mushroom trip or found Jesus swimming in the bongwater.
Nothing doing… he seemed to have been not on the 5-lane superhighway to Damascus when lightning struck, but going on his own uphill machete-chop through the jungle.
I think there’s a species of considered reflection and sober decision-making that has probably been respectfully suffixed with “complex” or “syndrome” in the hallowed journals of psychology.
Fellows about his age suddenly become aware of themselves in a new way, discard their sophomoric philosophical dodges and amateur hedonisms, and then quickly hide under the big rock of some preformed dogmatic nonsense before things begin to get too scary.
It remains to be seen, I suppose, whether or not he will avoid that fate.
But he seems pretty well-immunized.
I guess this born-again mental process is independent after all from the dogma-vultures who feed on its victims.…
He’s kinda high on righteousness and rhetoric right now.
He’s been reading Sartre on the French Resistance and you can tell he’s drawing parallels.
He thinks he’s living in a country under occupation by vile aristocrats and their frightened toadies and, well, there’s not much to argue with in that interpretation except that it lends itself to extremes of melodrama and a certain urgency, if, that is, you’ve got a newfound concern for ethics or somesuch.
Well, it’s interesting to be put under the magnifying glass in this way.
To the extent that open-ended observations like these need a response, the response should probably be centered on three questions that are raised:
1) Is my newfound interest in washing my hands of financial support of the government a symptom of a more general personal renaissance in the area of ethics?
2) Is this a stereotypical Seasons of a Man’s Life-style thing that I’m just embroidering with my own eccentricities (and therefore this blog is potentially as banal as the love poetry of the pubescent)?
3) Is it akin to a “born-again” religious conversion?
I’m tempted to start by making observations of my own, starting with the fact that all of this interesting examination might just be a fancy way of trying to evade question #4:
But is he right?
Amateur psychoanalysis can be a nice ad hominem way of trying to make an uncomfortable argument go away.
(It can also be a way of getting further mileage out of the freak-show-like interest one can take in a kook with his bizarre manifestos and such — and if this is your motivation, I can sympathize with you, but forgive me if I don’t feel like indulging you.)
To questions #1–3 I may have to plead a reluctant “no contest.”
I do feel like I have been taking questions of ethics a lot more seriously lately, and my decision to start this experiment is a symptom of that.
Whether this is something that can be dismissed as a “syndrome,” as question #2 suggests, or if instead it is just an overdue maturing of my outlook is something you can decide for yourself.
As for the religious speculation, well, I guess in part it depends on your answer to #2.
Religious answers to big questions aren’t really my style, I’ll tell you that much.
I tend to see religious answers as ways of avoiding questions or wishing them away.
That said, I’ll admit there’s more about this universe of ours that remains mysterious to me than there is that I’m pretty clear about, and there’s a lot of room in that mystery for stuff I’d be willing to adopt a worshipful attitude toward if any such thing shows its face to me, so I’m not going to write off the religious thing entirely.
And as I read about the history of tax resistance, civil disobedience, and such, and about people who stood up to governments bravely in ways I hope I’d be capable of — I’m finding that a lot of my role models and heroes have taken motivation and inspiration from religion.
So I’m becoming a lot less hostile and dismissive of the religious outlook than I used to be.
Religion for many people seems to be a way of avoiding questions of truth and responsibility, but for some people it’s a method for relentlessly confronting these same questions.
Dear Picket Line—
Maybe this is a dumb question, but… You’ve embarked on this bold experiment of yours, and it looks like you’re hoping other people will join you.
My question is: why do you care?
I mean, what is your ethical center?
Where do you get the notion that we should all treat each other in a decent fashion?
—Salmos Catorce
Dear Salmos—
That’s not a dumb question.
That’s one of those advanced, extra credit, smart questions.
My ethical philosophy started where most people start: absorbing the ethical guidance from the people around me when I was a child, trying to systematize that advice into principles I could apply in a more general way, and looking to law, philosophy, or the God hypothesis to try to find some sort of concrete grounding behind these principles.
Most of these principles, and certainly most of the hypothetical foundations behind them, disintegrated from their own contradictions, absurdities, and unlikelihoods as I got older, and so eventually I became an ethical skeptic.
I didn’t think there was any way to objectively ground ethics, and I figured it was probably effectively a subset of aesthetics.
And so I started to live a life freed from concern about transgressing phantom ethical boundaries — not even as an egoist, but something more haphazard and arbitrary.
Had I been of the mettle of a Nietzchean übermensch, I might have become a Nietzchean übermensch, or maybe a Randoid demi-hero, or quite possibly just a dick.
As it was, I mostly became sophomoric and inconsiderate.
Somewhere along the line, I discovered that I’d misevaluated ethics as being something that must either be given a rigorous foundation in reason or must be discarded as a superstitious façade covering up or justifying social manipulation, personal prejudices, and cultural convention.
I realized that I was making ethical evaluations all the time, as much as I might pretend to believe that no such things were possible, and that these ethical evaluations were as real parts of my experience as, say, color.
I couldn’t run away from them without going through grotesque internal distortions of reality (like trying to pretend that I didn’t see “blue” because I couldn’t find a rational foundation for color).
So I decided to bite the bullet and try to accept ethics rather than try to rationalize it away.
So my “center” is an ethical “sixth sense” where I look at some situation and intuitively know “that’d be wrong” and steer away from it.
Perhaps that means that ethics reduces to aesthetics after all.
Reason is a participant in my ethical evaluations, and in my evaluation of my ethics, but I don’t expect it to take the lead, and I don’t expect ethics to be derived from reason.
There may be no reason to serve God and not the Devil at any particular moment.
A lot of religion seems to be an attempt to invent reasons — God’s commandments, or divine judgment with punishment in the afterlife, for instance.
But I’m kind of fond of imagining the existentialist atheist saying — ha! there’s no God, and no reason to serve God and not the Devil, but I’m going to serve God anyway!
Wheeee!
It’s a performance I’m putting on for myself.
Or a “Choose Your Own Adventure” book writ large.
Nothing matters, ultimately, except to the extent that we decide that it matters.
No God will fill out a performance evaluation for me.
I won’t be reincarnated as a prince or a lamprey.
Our suffering and triumph means nothing in the greater scheme of things.
Cruel and evil people prosper and then die old and satisfied in their sleep while innocent children have their arms ripped off by bombs and die of dysentery.
Neither get redemptions from a heavenly accountant — from the perspective of eternity, their books are already balanced and their accounts are of no account.
My bones will crumble to dust in no time at all, and my name will be forgotten as quickly.
And I am going to try to be a good person anyway because that’s what I want to do with my life.
The growing respectability of torture in the United States and its coming legalization, among other things, have sent me back to Hannah Arendt to look for some recommendations for how to proceed.
She was a refugee from, and a student of, a time and place in which
…the few rules and standards according to which men used to tell right from wrong, and which were invoked to judge or justify others and themselves, and whose validity were supposed to be self-evident to every sane person either as a part of divine or of natural law.… without much notice… collapsed almost overnight, and then it was as though morality suddenly stood revealed in the original meaning of the word, as a set of mores, customs and manners, which could be exchanged for another set with hardly more trouble than it would take to change the table manners of an individual or a people.
And she put a lot of effort into trying to understand how this happened, and what, if anything, we can do to interrupt it.
I’ve lately been reading a collection of her writings called Responsibility and Judgment in which much of the material directly attacks this problem, and most of the rest at least touches on it.
The most and greatest evil, Arendt believes, is not done by wicked or evil people, but “by people who never made up their mind to be either bad or good” — “by nobodies, that is, by human beings who refuse to be persons.”
Such people, in times when the conventional morality that serves societies reasonably well most of the time goes through a polar shift in which the “thou shalt not”s become “thou shalt”s, go along to get along — having no habit of using anything but conventional morality as a guide.
This evil — “banal” evil as she famously put it — is committed, according to her theory, by people who do not think.
This isn’t to say that these people are not intelligent, or cultured,1 or knowledgeable.
“Thinking” has a particular meaning in Arendt’s framework: it is a process of internal dialog, one that is necessarily done in withdrawal from society and real-world concerns (that is, you can’t think at the same time you are working or conversing).
This withdrawal she calls “solitude” but it is a solitude that you share with yourself in a peculiar duality that enables the dialog to take place: you split in two and converse with yourself.
Thinking is not a method for determining hard-and-fast eternal truths about good & evil, but is a process of doubting and testing.
It is related to remembering, in that if you think over what you have done and try to fit it into your life story, this is one way of remembering it.
In contrast, if you do not think, and therefore forget your own actions, you are capable of doing anything “just as my courage would be absolutely reckless if pain, for instance, were an experience immediately forgotten.” …
“The greatest evildoers are those who don’t remember because they have never given thought to the matter, and, without remembrance, nothing can hold them back.”
If you do not think, you are “rootless” — at the mercy of the winds that might blow you into some new, pathological moral convention.
It’s not necessarily the case that having roots means that you’re wisely-rooted, but it does mean that you have a stake in your own personality and self-imposed limits on what you are capable of doing.
Without these roots, you have no limits, you are capable of anything, and your own character is a matter of indifference to you.
In short: you are dangerous.
Thinking, which is to say being in dialog with yourself, is what gives you this stake in your own character — it “results in conscience as its by-product.”
You don’t want to be spending your time in dialog with a monster:
“If I do wrong I am condemned to live together with a wrongdoer in an unbearable intimacy.”
This is of such importance that, as Socrates put it, it is better to be wronged than to do wrong.2
Arendt admits that while this may sound like a nice aphorism, its opposite seems more plausible.
But “while many prefer to do wrong for their own benefit rather than suffer wrong, no one will prefer to live together with a thief or a murderer or a liar.
This is what people forget who praise the tyrant who has come into power through murder and fraud.”
But here this “living together with” metaphor seems to be stretched too far.
If conscience is a by-product of thinking, because thinking includes this need to live in harmony with ourselves — that is if we are not expected to have some sort of pre-existing moral yardstick available through reason or divine revelation or what have you — then why do I not want to live in harmony with a self who is a murderer or a thief?
The reason why I do not want to live with a murderer, assuming I do not have a pre-existing moral yardstick by which I judge murder to be wrong, is because I’m afraid of being murdered; I don’t want to live with a thief because I don’t want to be robbed; and I don’t want to live with a liar because I do not want to be deceived.
But you’re not going to rob or murder yourself, and if you lie to yourself you may believe with some justification that you are doing this to your own advantage.
Why would you not want to live with yourself as a liar, thief, or murderer unless you already held these things in contempt, in which case the whole exercise of trying to determine who you would be willing to live with as a way of bootstrapping your moral judgment seems beside-the-point.
The living-with-a-liar thing seems to be the crucial part: if you live with a liar, you cannot trust the inner dialog with which, by thinking, you pursue the truth you presumably love.
Perhaps if you love truth, and therefore do not lie to yourself, an abhorrence for murder and theft will necessarily follow.
I see another problem: if this need to live in harmony with yourself is so vitally important that you would rather suffer wrong than commit it, rather be murdered than murder, rather drink hemlock than go into dishonorable exile, and so forth, then it seems likely that this will override any but the most extreme love of truth.
If you and the self you are in dialog with can achieve this crucial harmony by agreeing to a comfortable lie, and the alternative is to be in disharmony over an uncomfortable truth, what’s holding you back from embracing the lie?
This love of truth and this need to live in harmony with yourself also seem so rare to me that the question of how to encourage them seems no easier than the question we started with — how to discourage people from participating in bureaucratic massacre and the like.
How do you encourage people to love truth or to strive for integrity?
For that matter, where did I get the crazy idea that it is wrong to torture someone?
Is such a notion even really part of my character, or is it some custom that I have rootlessly blown up against and that I am vulnerable to being swept away from in a change of wind?
In truth, I am most repulsed by torture in the abstract and the less I know of the victims and perpetrators and of the perpetrators’ motives.
As things get more specific, I can get frightened (if I imagine myself or those I love being tortured) or I can even take some delight in the thought (if I imagine, say, Attorney General Gonzalez getting some first-hand experience of some of the techniques he’s helped to provide legal cover for).
Maybe my expressions of moral revulsion around torture are a sort of gambit — an attempt at prompting reciprocal altruism.
I make an explicit promise to eschew torture even when I may be indifferent or hostile to its victims in the hopes that this will encourage other people to behave the same way to me and those I love.
Doesn’t seem like this would make much headway.
Pious incantations of the Golden Rule or the Categorical Imperative are easily made — enforcing reciprocal altruism requires a lot more, including being able to verify and observe and monitor those you’re reciprocating with.
So I’d have to believe that these incantations have some powerful persuasive force all their own, without an effective mechanism of enforcement.
Perhaps I can claim to have the force of Reason on my side (lord knows, many a philosopher has tried), or, even more persuasively, the Word of God.
Socrates himself made a nod in this direction, suggesting that the mass of people who do not think, and therefore cannot self-generate moral behavior, must be held in line by a myth of a final judgment and threats of eternal punishment.
Such things have been tried with at best limited success, but nobody with half a brain really believes them (though many profess them).
We “are committed (it would seem) to think of conscience as an organ that will react without hope for rewards and without fear of punishment.”
Nietzsche would call this appeal to morality a gambit of the weak — if you think you can impose your preferences by force, you have no need to appeal to some universal standard of right and wrong, you just do your thing; on the other hand, if you are defenseless, big talk may be all you’ve got.
Moral behavior might, however, be a kind of demonstration of strength.
In the same way that a bird with colorful feathers is advertising to potential mates that it has plenty of resources to waste on bright plumage (and so it must be one fit and clever bird) — a person who engages in moral living is announcing a cocky unconcern for the loss of whatever advantages come from being immoral or amoral.
In contrast, for a person who really is in a position of weakness — someone whose children are starving, or someone addicted to drugs — morality is an expensive luxury.
Clarence Marsh Case, in The Social Psychology of Passive Resistance, points out that Franklin Henry Giddings had made this argument in his Democracy and Empire:
“Not less are all the higher virtues — philanthropy, compassion, and forgiveness — manifestations of power…
Moreover, it is only the men that have energy to spare who are normally altruistic.
On the physiological side, altruism is a mode of expenditure of any surplus energy that has been left over from successful individual struggle.
The meek shall inherit the earth, not because they are meek, but because, taking one generation with another, it is only the mighty that are or can be meek, and because the mighty — if normally evolved — are also by differentiation meek.”
Giddings is here explicitly responding to Nietzsche.
―♇
But that’s all very speculative.
Assuming morality and moral philosophy aren’t just some sort of fang-flashing, and if you aren’t buying the questionable moral foundations perennially discovered in Reason or God, what is there to keep you interested in ideas of right and wrong?
What motive do you have to evaluate your own actions by this sort of standard?
I’ve toyed with the idea that in life we have one shot to be the sort of person we admire, and that this is motivation enough:
Nothing matters, ultimately, except to the extent that we decide that it matters.
No God will fill out a performance evaluation for me.
I won’t be reincarnated as a prince or a lamprey.
Our suffering and triumph means nothing in the greater scheme of things.
Cruel and evil people prosper and then die old and satisfied in their sleep while innocent children have their arms ripped off by bombs and die of dysentery.
Neither get redemptions from a heavenly accountant — from the perspective of eternity, their books are already balanced and their accounts are of no account.
My bones will crumble to dust in no time at all, and my name will be forgotten as quickly.
And I am going to try to be a good person anyway because that’s what I want to do with my life.
But I still found myself relying on what I called “an ethical ‘sixth sense’ ” — this mysterious conscience.
But of today’s villains, the torturers and terrorists and demagogues, who’s to say they don’t have their own sixth sense or that they aren’t enacting the character they admire?
Arendt said that this “sixth sense” is misleading: “these feelings indicate conformity and nonconformity, they don’t indicate morality.”:
Conscience supposedly is a way of feeling beyond reason and argument and of knowing through sentiment what is right and wrong.
What has been revealed beyond doubt, I think, is the fact that such feelings indeed exist, that people feel guilty or feel innocent, but that alas, these feelings are no reliable indications, are in fact no indications at all, of right and wrong.
But at some point I must feel that I wouldn’t want to live with myself if I were to do X, Y, or Z.
Why wouldn’t I want to live with a torturer?
Because I would feel guilty, I would be repulsed at myself, all of this because of this same unreliable ethical sixth sense.
I also can’t help but feel that there are reasons why some things are right and others wrong that lie outside of me — it would be wrong for me to torture someone because of something to do with them, not just something to do with me.
Could it really be that there is nothing more at stake in moral questions than my own opinion of myself?
Though Arendt claims that among the Nazis, none of “these highly cultivated murderers… wrote a poem worth remembering or a piece of music worth listening to or painted a picture that anybody would care to hang on his walls… [because] no gifts will withstand the loss of integrity which you lose when you have lost this most common capacity for thought and remembrance.”
Arendt believes this to be an entirely negative standard — that is it only tells you what you cannot do not what you should do.
In other words, I cannot do X because I could not live with an X-doer.
I don’t understand why you cannot just as easily think something like “I couldn’t live with someone who would neglect the opportunity to do Y or who would fail to do my Z obligation.”
This variety of inquiry into ethics differs from the traditional philosophical approach.
The idea here is that the human experience of moral judgment can be usefully analyzed without reference to some theoretical objective moral standard — thereby sidestepping the traditional philosophical quagmires.
Moral judgment, in this school of thought, is a variety of sensation: a subjective qualitative experience that doesn’t have a qualitative counterpart in the objective world — in the same way that there is a continuous spectrum of electromagnetic frequencies in the objective world, but the sensation of color only exists in the subjective world.
Or, perhaps more closely analogous, “disgust” is a mental evaluation of the state of the world, but not a characteristic of that world — only a state of the mind that evaluates it.
If you look at morality in this way, you can go on to design experiments that show how people morally evaluate scenarios, what their brains do when they do so, and how this correlates with their behavior.
And you can make educated guesses for how natural selection might have favored certain varieties of moral evaluation in our ancestors.
The promise of this approach is that you aren’t just arguing ethical philosophy (which can seem pretty fruitless), but you’re actually collecting data and testing hypotheses — mmmm… the delicious taste of Science!
However:
Here is the worry.
The scientific outlook has taught us that some parts of our subjective experience are products of our biological makeup and have no objective counterpart in the world.
The qualitative difference between red and green, the tastiness of fruit and foulness of carrion, the scariness of heights and prettiness of flowers are design features of our common nervous system, and if our species had evolved in a different ecosystem or if we were missing a few genes, our reactions could go the other way.
Now, if the distinction between right and wrong is also a product of brain wiring, why should we believe it is any more real than the distinction between red and green?
And if it is just a collective hallucination, how could we argue that evils like genocide and slavery are wrong for everyone, rather than just distasteful to us?
It may be fruitful for us to discover why certain people under certain circumstances are morally repulsed by genocide, and other people under other circumstances are not, but the reason people dive into the philosophical quagmires rather than just leaving this to the scientists is that they’d like to go one step further and say that, in addition, one of those moral evaluations of genocide is the correct one, in much the same way as a mathematical truth is not just a point-of-view.
A scientific, descriptive understanding of moral sensations seems to leave something out.
It threatens to reduce ethics to an arbitrary drive evolution has planted in us for reasons that have more to do with our dead ancestors than the living neighbors we practice it on.
It seems to pull ethics outside of the realm of argument and make a mere phenomenon of it.
But even at this extreme, the consequences aren’t quite so bad as this.
Note that people sometimes critically examine their instinctual evaluations and find them to be irrational and in need of rational augmentation.
See, for instance, the “five second rule” by which food that has just been dropped to the floor moves from the safe-to-eat category into the too-vile-to-pass-our-lips category after a brief passage of time.
This rule, or something like it, is something that many of us feel to be true, viscerally, but know to be hogwash, epidemiologically.
It isn’t difficult to believe that this feeling of disgust over dropped food is probably a heuristic in the form of a feeling — one that evolved to protect us from dangerously contaminated food — and that dropped food doesn’t become inherently or objectively disgusting when the subjective edibility timer runs out.
But knowing the purpose and origins of our instinctual perception of disgust — knowing that it’s a mere phenomenon and an artifact of how evolution shaped our brains — doesn’t end the story, but provides a jumping-off point for rational refinement of the original sub-rational evaluation.
It’s possible that the same is true of investigations into moral evaluation.
Most of us have a semi-rational ethical worldview that we like to think we conform to, and a moral “feeling” apparatus that operates, more-or-less in parallel, at a pre-rational or even subconscious level.
The more we know about how that apparatus operates, the more we can anticipate when and how it will conflict with the ethics we would choose consciously and rationally.
Then we can prepare and adjust accordingly.
Virtue is found in the exercise of means (wishing for the correct
ends is presumably more a matter of wisdom than virtue). The
exercise of means (or the decision not to) is a matter of deliberation and
choice, and so is in our power, and therefore so is our virtue.
You are responsible for being reasonably informed about what you need to know
to make the right decisions in the circumstances you encounter, and if you
ignore this responsibility (or if you actively contribute to your own
ignorance, for instance by being drunk or by looking away from some
inconvenient truth), you cannot use your ignorance as an excuse for vicious
actions.
Since virtue is a habit (as is vice), it may be a choice to initially
acquire a vice or to neglect a virtue, but once you have
done this habitually, it becomes less voluntary over time. This is
interesting for a couple of reasons: first, if virtues and vices become less
voluntary as they become more habitual, it would seem that they become less
praiseworthy or blameworthy also; second, it seems to create another
obstacle in the path to becoming a virtuous person if you aren’t
one already — how do you go about changing bad habits if they aren’t even
very voluntary any longer? (Aristotle does not yet address either of these
points, but I hope he does eventually.)
In some recorded lectures about the
Nicomachean Ethics that I was listening to during a recent leisurely
train ride down California,
Joseph Koturksi emphasized that Aristotle defined moral virtue in particular as a habit of choosing the golden mean — that is to say that it differs from other varieties of habit in not constricting choice but in exhibiting itself as choosing.
It seems from this that the lack of moral virtue can take two forms, or a
combination of the two: not choosing, or choosing poorly.
(I suppose a third variety would be a failure to make correct choosing
habitual, but my reading of Aristotle suggests that this habituation
is an automatic process, and so its absence would be more suggestive of, say,
brain damage, than of anything correctable by philosophy.)
Anyway: “habit” in the case of moral virtue isn’t meant as a sort of
unthinking, repetitive, by-rote sort of behavior. Point made.
Next, Aristotle addresses the argument that while everybody aims for the
apparent good, what appears to be good to each of us is not under
our control but is just a given part of our temperament or constitution or
some such. Aristotle says that if this is true, then you aren’t really to be
blamed for deeds you perform under the misapprehension that you’re doing the
right thing. However, he says that to some extent, you are responsible for
your own temperament and constitution, and to that extent you can inherit
responsibility for the misdeeds you perform under its influence.
But in any case, if our virtues are voluntary and we can be praised for them,
our vices are too, and we can be blamed for them.
From here, for most of the rest of the Nicomachean Ethics, we’re going to go
into an in-depth look at particular virtues. The rest of this book will look
at courage and temperance. Book four will concern liberality, magnificence,
pride, industriousness, good temper, friendliness, truthfulness, bonhomie,
and the quasi-virtue of shame. Book five is all about justice. Book six
concerns the intellectual virtues. Book seven concerns continence and also
contains a discussion of pleasure that will be continued in book ten.
Several days ago my sweetie and I were relaxing at home with a
DVD from the library: the movie
Secretary.
It’s a silly story about a mousy young woman (played by Maggie Gyllenhaal,
who also, coincidentally, played the vivacious tax resister in
Stranger than
Fiction) who becomes the secretary of an eccentric lawyer and who
finds her job transforming into an erotic dominance/submission scene in which
she learns to play the submissive and ends up personally flowering and
maturing in the course of doing so.
It’s not a very deep film, but some of her character’s comments about the
pleasures of submission — unthinking obedience to the commands of a trusted
dominant — and the sort of confidence and, oddly, “freedom” that results from
this, lodged in my head and got me thinking about this and that.
Much of this “freedom” is freedom from having to make up your own mind and
make your own decisions and assert your own risky initiative. What am I
going to do? Whatever the dominant wants me to do or tells me to do. If
that’s always the right answer, it makes deciding a snap and much
less of a burden, and permits you (or seems to permit you) to shift most of
the burden of the responsibility for the consequences onto the dominant
“decider.”
In a bedroom scene, that’s all fun and games, but when such things come out
of the bedroom and into society at large, this sort of evasion of
responsibility can be very dangerous. Hannah Arendt spent some time analyzing
Adolf Eichmann as someone who had decided to renounce his will and devote
himself to carrying out his Fuhrer’s will; once he was caught and put on
trial for this, he pathetically tried to excuse his behavior by saying that
having made himself an agent of the Fuhrer’s whims, he was no longer
able to behave according to his remaining ethical instincts.
I quoted Arne Johan Vetlesen’s summary of Arendt’s
argument: “superfluousness represents a temptation: it holds the
promise of an existence devoid of (enacted) human agency, hence free
of the burdens of responsibility and guilt, as well as hurt and loss.”
Vetlesen says that indulging this temptation not only dangerously enables you
to commit evil, but is a sort of evil itself:
Morally speaking, permitting oneself to be dehumanized, to be robbed of
one’s autonomy (Kant), is in itself no lesser sin than participating in the
dehumanization of others; it entails permitting oneself to become an
instrument in the realization of ends posited by others.
The military chain of command is another dangerous variety of
D&S
game in which essentially unquestioning obedience is expected. I suspect that
a craving for submission and for freedom from the burden of decision-making
and its consequences is a strong motivation for many people who join the
military. This burden can feel especially heavy to young people just
emerging from home and from institutional education into the freedom of
adulthood and all of the responsibility it entails.
In a Christian context, this is explicit: the Christian accepts Christ as his
or her Lord and Master, and says Thy Will Be Done, I will deny myself and take
up my cross daily, and so forth. Kant, for his part, thought that an act was
really virtuous only if it was unpleasant, painful, or difficult — whip me! beat me! make me virtuous!
How do you identify and correct for a decadent parody of virtue that really
amounts to a responsibility-denying
D&S
scene? That is, how do you know whether you’re being virtuous or whether
you’re submitting to a freedom-restricting straitjacket in the name of virtue?
How do you avoid getting in a situation where you do the wrong thing, but
“can’t help it” because you’ve obligated yourself to submit to Christ’s
teachings, or to think of the greatest good for the greatest number, or to
maintain Army discipline, or to obey the categorical imperative, or whatever
your dom happens to be?
And how would you defend against the argument that Aristotle’s model of virtue
is essentially a
D&S
scene in which a mental model of virtue is the
dom?
One possible line of defense would be to note that, in Aristotle’s scheme
(unlike Kant’s, for instance), virtuous acts are not necessarily painful or
difficult or against your inclinations — indeed, often quite the opposite:
virtue is a variety of excellence and an important path toward
eudaimonia — flourishing, thriving, happiness.
So at least this isn’t an
S&M thing,
where you martyr yourself and then take pleasure in your suffering. Also, as
Joseph Koturski pointed out, moral virtue
is the habit of choosing well, so it doesn’t unburden you of the
need to choose at all. To the extent that a
D&S
scene is partially about freedom-from-choice, an internal, non-dogmatic
dom doesn’t do the trick
(whereas a Categorical Imperative or a scriptural Jesus might do).
A few months after writing this entry, I picked up A Testament to Freedom, a collection of the writings of Dietrich Bonhoeffer.
In one of his early works on Christian Ethics, he wrote:
For Christians there are no ethical principles by means of which they could
perhaps civilize themselves. Nor can yesterday ever be decisive for my moral
action today. Rather must a direct relationship to God’s will be ever sought
afresh. I do not do something again today because it seemed to me to be good
yesterday, but because the will of God points out this way to me today. This
is the great moral renewal through Jesus, the renunciation of principles, of
rulings, in the words of the Bible, of the law, and this follows as a
consequence of the Christian idea of God; for if there was a generally valid
moral law, then there would be a way from the human to God — I would have my
principles, so I would believe myself assured sub specie
aeternitatis. So, to some extent, I would have control over my
relationship to God, so there would be a moral action without immediate
relationship to God. And, most important of all, in that case I would once
again become a slave to my principles. I would sacrifice our most precious
gift, freedom.
It seems like up to now, Aristotle has been speaking of justice as a set of
conventions. Either it is explicitly a matter of being law-abiding, or it’s
a matter of being “fair” where fairness is defined according to the
prevailing community standards.
But in the seventh section of the fifth book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle says that political justice is only partially conventional.
There is also a “natural” component: “that which everywhere has the same force and does not exist by people’s thinking this or that.”
(If you’re following along in another edition, this section and the ones around it are divided up differently in various translations.
This is true for all of the books, but seems especially varied here.)
All along, there has been this tension about whether justice is to be
invented or discovered — that is, whether it is solely
the product of human invention or whether it preexists and its human-created
approximations are more-or-less faithful to it. Aristotle has been walking
along the boundary between these two positions: trying to discover
the virtues (like justice), but trying to discover it via anthropology,
that is by examining how people conventionally discuss and enact the
virtues. Now he attempts to face the issue head-on.
Aristotle entertains the idea (promoted by the Sophists) that all justice is
conventional, and that the only natural laws are things like the laws of
physics (“as fire burns both here and in Persia”) while laws of justice are
absolutely mutable and might as well be arbitrary.
He says that there’s a grain of truth to this: certainly it would be possible
for any particular proposed “natural” law of justice, to imagine a nation
in which that law is inverted so that what we think is just, they outlaw as
unjust, and vice versa, and to imagine the people of that nation internalizing
that law in that way.
But Aristotle doesn’t think this is the end of the question. He says that
there may still be such thing as “natural” law, even though people may be
able to override or contradict it with conventional law. He compares this
to being right- or left-handed. You can probably train a right- or
left-handed child to switch hands or to become ambidextrous. This doesn’t
mean that handedness is completely conventional, only that although it is
natural it is moldable by human effort.
To Aristotle there is a natural standard by which conventional justice can
itself be judged. Although what is just by human enactment is subject to
change and is to some extent arbitrary, there are better and worse examples
of these things, and “but one [constitution] which is everywhere by nature
the best” (it’s unclear whether he means that for each polis, there is a best
constitution for it, or whether he means that there is a single best
constitution that all political groups would be best off adopting; the
translators tend to keep this ambiguous but seem to me to lean toward the
latter).
From here, things get confusing. This sounds like it’s saying something
important, but I can’t for the life of me figure out what:
Of things just and lawful each is related as the universal to its particulars;
for the things that are done are many, but of them each is one, since it is
universal.
Now of Justs and Lawfuls each bears to the acts which embody and exemplify it
the relation of an universal to a particular; the acts being many, but each
of the principles only singular, because each is an universal.
Okay; that’s not so important after all… it’s just a preamble for what
follows (back to Ross again):
There is a difference between the act of injustice and what is unjust, and
between the act of justice and what is just; for a thing is unjust by nature
or by enactment; and this very thing, when it has been done, is an act of
injustice, but before it is done is not yet that but is unjust. [Ditto for
just actions.]
What does all that mean? Just that an act is an act of injustice when it
is acted out, but when an act is only contemplated it is not yet an act of
injustice but may be in the category of things that would be unjust if they
were acted out? Is he just defining terms, or is there more to it than that?
I hope things become more clear in the following sections.
I’m also thankful for The Joy of Curmudgeonry, who brings us an interesting corrective to human presumptions in drawing up ethical systems, in the form of Thomas Carlyle’s Schwein’sche Weltansicht.
What if all of our contemporary moral discourse were a kind of cargo cult in which we had picked up fragments of a long lost, once-coherent and -rational moral philosophy, and had proceeded forward with these fragments, not really knowing what we were doing, and had constructed a bunch of nonsense that didn’t work and could not work in principle?
Alasdair MacIntyre, in After Virtue (), argues that this indeed is what happened, and this explains why our moral discourse is such a mess.
Why is it that when we argue with each other about moral issues — war and
peace, liberty or equality, life or choice, family values or gay rights, what
have you — we make our case in a form that seems to be one of logical,
rational argument (“my point of view is true because…”), but the effect of
what we say seems to be only like that of imperative statements (“Join me in
supporting…”) or exclamations (“…is the bestest!”)? Why do pro-life folks and
pro-choice folks (for instance) keep arguing with each other when there is no
resolution to their argument?
MacIntyre believes that we are unconsciously reenacting forms of argument that once made sense, since people once did have a common ground of morality they could advance together from rationally, but that we have since lost this in a Tower of Babel-like catastrophe.
As a result, our moral arguments today are interminable because the values
they express are essentially incommensurable. Though the claims of the
emotivists are not
universally and necessarily true, they happen to be true for contemporary
moral philosophy: when people make moral arguments today they really
are just making imperative statements or exclamations of
(dis)approval while disguising these as rational arguments about facts.
Modern moral philosophy has adopted the idea that all moral systems must eventually descend on certain first principles that everyone must choose for themselves and for which there are no rational criteria for a correct choice: you cannot get an “ought” from an “is” as they say.
As a result, the only way you can defend any results you derive from such a moral framework to someone else who does not share that framework is in a form that ultimately reduces to “my first principles are better than your first principles, nyaah nyaah.”
This means that all of this arguing is necessarily for nought. And modern
moral philosophy has been absolutely unsuccessful in finding any way out of
this predicament.
As a result, the emotivist explanation of moral argument is the dominant and most rational one, and so people who engage in moral arguments are essentially trying to manipulate others and at the same time to resist being manipulated, knowing on some level that there is no rational resolution, which leads to the perpetual histrionic impasse and jousting with talking-points that keeps the television news networks and political parties in business.
Although a number of modern philosophers have suggested that this is a
necessary feature of moral philosophy — that there are no right answers in
ethics or that the whole field of inquiry is some sort of an illusion — MacIntyre says that this state of affairs isn’t necessarily true but
is really just the result of the catastrophe that shattered a once-coherent
ethics.
Our current concept of “the moral” was invented in the 17th–19th centuries to cover “rules of conduct which are neither theological nor legal nor aesthetic.” The philosophical project of justifying these rules developed along with it.
The classical world didn’t have this concept.
The words we appropriated for it — moralis or etikos — meant something more like our word “character.” The failure of this philosophical project of justifying our received moral rules is “the historical background against which the predicaments of our own culture can become intelligible.”
MacIntyre works backwards through Kierkegaard, Kant, Diderot, and Hume, and
says that they were unable to find a rational ground for morality in choice,
in reason, or in passion and desire. Each was capable of decisively refuting
some of these grounds, but each failed to show that their own best guess was
capable of doing the job.
These philosophers had to fail because their project — to somehow derive morality from human nature — was incoherent and doomed.
The morality that these philosophers were trying to justify consisted of
surviving remnants of morality from an earlier time. The ancestor of these
morals were the virtues that Aristotle discussed in The
Nicomachean Ethics, in which ethics is considered to be the science of
how we govern our lives so as to best meet the ends of human living: the human
telos.
This scheme was modified by the various monotheisms that became dominant, so as to make God the source of our telos, to make this telos other-worldly (the Kingdom of God), and to make what Aristotle would have called vice or error into “sin.” But still, even after this transformation, ethical statements remain explicitly statements of fact: X is good because X will help you manifest your telos and is God’s plan for you.
Though the Christian philosophers thought that, since The Fall of Man, these facts were not available to us rationally, but only through the grace of God.
Later, the rationalists followed suit, and said that our reason is insufficient to choose our ends but is only suitable to choose means towards ends which are chosen in some other way (that “is”/“ought” thing).
Aristotle’s ethics has this structure: 1) Human beings are untutored; 2)
Human beings have a telos; 3) Ethics is the tutelage
necessary for human beings to achieve their telos.
Enlightenment philosophers abandoned the idea that there was such a thing as a
telos for human beings, and in so doing, lost the only way
of making ethical statements statements of fact. To Aristotle, an ethical
statement was true if the ethical rule it described did in fact help people
achieve their telos. Without reference to a
telos, ethical statements don’t mean anything at all.
So instead, enlightenment thinkers, who were okay with #1 (humans are untutored) and #3 (moral precepts are designed to correct human nature) stuck themselves with the impossible task of deriving #3 from #1. (Myself, I’m not sure this is quite as impossible as MacIntyre makes it out to be.
If I remember correctly, Aristotle didn’t start out with #2 as a premise, but derived it logically from his understanding of human nature, that is, from the same place he gets #1.
But in any case, MacIntyre says that the enlightenment thinkers did not want to saddle people with a telos, so perhaps it doesn’t matter whether or not it is derivable.)
The insistence that you cannot get an “ought” from an “is” that so perplexed
the moral philosophers is, MacIntyre insists, a bugbear that results from this
same undeclared premise: that humans have no telos, no
function, no purpose. For things with purposes, “is” may very well imply
“ought.” This is a watch; ergo it ought to tell the correct
time. A good watch tells the correct time; a bad watch is slow or fast or
right only twice a day. Good or bad for watches is embedded in the very
concept of watch. Similarly, if a person has a telos, he or
she may be more or less successful in meeting it, and his or her actions will
be more or less good, more or less ethical in Aristotelian terms, to the
extent that they assist in this attempt. And what these actions are is a
factual inquiry: is implies ought.
We still make our moral arguments and moral statements as if they had the form of falsifiable statements of fact, but we’ve lost the ability to articulate what makes them factual or falsifiable.
To try to fill in the gap, we’ve had to resort to a bunch of fictions.
For example, to replace teleology we have “utility”; to replace God’s revealed laws, we have the categorical imperative or “inalienable human rights” (or we continue to refer to God’s revealed laws but only in a way that makes them indistinguishable from the other merely emotive utterances of modern ethics).
These things are all just phantasmagorical placeholders that are designed to fill in the inconvenient and embarrassing gaps in moral theory, but that have no more real existence than do things like phlogiston or the luminiferous aether, which once served similar purposes in physics to the purposes “rights” and “utility” serve in modern ethical theories.
But still we continue to argue as though one of these gambits had succeeded
(though if we bother to investigate, we discover that none of them really
have). And yet we suspect that all of our moral discourse is a
machiavellian
struggle to manipulate and deceive each other. Our moral claims are
incommensurable because they have incompatible, largely fictional bases, and
so there is no reality or appeal to reality with which we can adjudicate
moral disputes.
This leads to petulant protest, a modern form of moral discourse, which is used because rational argument has no hope of succeeding.
The other dominant variety of moral discourse today is unmasking, in which foes discover each others’ moral pronouncements to be sham façades that mask selfish and arbitrary desires (hey, what do you know, Senator So-and-so is a hypocrite!).
This amounts to a parlor game, since everybody’s ethics have become incoherent and full of internal contradictions.
Along with such fictional devices as “right” and “utility,” the modern age
has created “effectiveness” as a fetish in moral argument. Effectiveness is
central to the character of the bureaucratic manager, who uses the myth of
managerial expertise to manipulate those being managed and to justify the
managers’ power. Like appeals to God, right, or utility, appeals to managerial
expertise disguise the ultimately expressive or imperative nature of the
utterance. The idea of managerial expertise implies a domain of real knowledge
about social structures and their inputs and outputs of which the manager has
specialized and true knowledge. This turns out to be a false claim. The basis
for managerial, bureaucratically-controlled societies (like ours) is that the
managers are thought to be value-neutral or value-independent, and actually
effective at assigning means to ends (though neither is really true).
The enlightenment also led to “fact”-based natural science and empiricism in general.
As part of this, the Aristotelian notion of ethics was split into two distinct philosophical disciplines: ethics (“what is good?”) and will (“how do intentions become actions?”).
Whereas in the Aristotelian view, explanations of human actions only make sense in reference to a hierarchy of goods and to the telos, in the mechanistic worldview, human action must be explained independently of any goods, intentions, purposes, reasons, or telos.
The social sciences of which managers are presumed to be experts are those in which the human subjects are seen in this manner.
This leads to a viewpoint from which it comes to appear as if the people being
manipulated by the practitioners of the social/managerial sciences do not have
any intention or purpose or telos of their own worth
respecting, but the same is implicitly not the case for the
manipulators and social scientists themselves, who must have intentions and
purposes for their actions to make any sense at all.
Social science (which includes economics) does not actually succeed, MacIntyre says, at deriving laws with predictive power.
Its “generalizations” are in no way scientific, but merely are dressed up like science.
This is because human affairs are systematically unpredictable, for several reasons: It is impossible in principle to predict the effects of the sorts of radically new conceptual innovations that occur in human history.
People cannot confidently predict even their own actions.
Chance trivialities can have large effects (what we would today call “the butterfly effect”).
Game-theory-like situations map poorly to real-life situations, and even so, they imply a necessary level of deceptiveness and recursive counter-plotting that makes real-world scientific observation and prediction difficult. (For example, during the Vietnam war, war-theorists working for the United States government cleverly created simulations and projections for victory using the best data they had at their disposal — data that was being systematically falsified by other elements of the same government who were using their own game-theory-ish reasons for using deceit in the service of victory.)
That said, there are some predictabilities in human behavior: There are some,
sometimes unconscious but justifiable, expectations of each others’ behavior
that allow us to engage in such social actions as scheduling and coordination.
There are statistical regularities in human action. Certain regularities of
nature place constraints on human possibility. Certain regularities of social
life also have predictive power (for instance, if your parents have more
money, you will probably have more educational opportunity).
People simultaneously want to make the world predictable (to assist in the success of their plans) and to make themselves unpredictable (to preserve their freedom).
For this reason, all we really should expect from social scientists are “usually”s.
Managerial pretensions to expertise (and thereby to the power and money that come with positions like President of the United States or Chief Executive Officer) are based on exaggerated and unfounded claims for the theoretical precision and accuracy of the social sciences.
When somebody claims to be doing something because of managerial expertise, you can be sure they are really just disguising their own desire or arbitrary preference, just the same as if they claimed to be fulfilling the will of god, maximizing utility, or respecting inalienable human rights.
Nonetheless, the contemporary vision of the world is bureaucratically
Weberian — Max Weber
mixed with Erving
Goffman. Goffman’s sociological point of view presupposes morals to be
false or at least irrelevant. It is honor, or the regard of others, that
takes its place as a motivator.
MacIntyre says that modern society found itself in much the same position as that of the Pacific islanders who had a set of taboos they were unable to explain to the missionaries and explorers who visited them.
Whatever reasons had originally led to the establishment of the taboos had long since vanished, and so all they could do when asked to explain their odd customs was to say, “but to do otherwise would be taboo.” MacIntyre says that Kamehameha Ⅱ was able to abolish the taboo system abruptly and by fiat precisely because it had no foundation underneath it anymore.
(I’m reminded of Hannah Arendt’s recollection of Nazi Germany as a time and
place where “…the few rules and standards according to which men used to tell
right from wrong, and which were invoked to judge or justify others and
themselves, and whose validity were supposed to be self-evident to every sane
person either as a part of divine or of natural law.… without much notice…
collapsed almost overnight, and then it was as though morality suddenly stood
revealed in the original meaning of the word, as a set of mores, customs and
manners, which could be exchanged for another set with hardly more trouble
than it would take to change the table manners of an individual or a people.”)
MacIntyre says that for those of us who have inherited the Western moral tradition, Nietzsche was our Kamehameha.
Nietzsche thought he was abolishing morality in general, but in fact, MacIntyre says, he was only pointing out the futility of the enlightenment project of providing a rational justification for the fragmentary remnants of classical ethics — our taboos.
If the classical ethical philosopher asked “what sort of person am I to
become, and how?” the modern ethical philosopher asked “what taboos must I
follow, and why?” It was a doomed project, because the taboos had become
dislodged from their original justifications, and the whole framework in which
those justifications made sense had been abandoned as part of the
enlightenment. To a modern philosopher like
John Rawls, for
instance, the virtues are nothing but tendencies to obey the taboos, with the
taboos being somehow more fundamental than the virtues.
What’s the alternative?
In the background of our struggles with moral philosophy and in the virtues we sympathize with but don’t understand enough to be able to justify, there is the ghost of an earlier and more coherent ethical system.
We may be able to retrace our steps and recover it.
The characteristics of “heroic” societies are revealed in the myths of
antiquity — not necessarily because these myths represent the realities of
the times they depict, but because the cultures that used and conveyed those
myths defined their own cultures in relation to them. In these societies,
everyone had a role and a purpose just by virtue of being born into a
particular station in a particular society with relations to particular
people. Nobody is defined by their “hidden depths” or their inner lives, but
by their actions relative to their roles; a person is what a person
does. Morality and social structure are the same thing; there isn’t
even a concept of morality as distinct from, independent of, or superior to
the particular social structure. You can’t “step outside” your society and
judge its moral system in comparison to some other system. Life is a
story that ends, tragically and in defeat, with death. A story like a
saga isn’t just incidentally a story about a life, but is a representation of
a life that is already understood to have the form of a story. Virtue is what
enables you to fulfill the role you have and to conduct yourself in your
story. Contra Nietzsche, the hero does not assert his arbitrary will, but
accepts his role as being a real thing worthy of respect; the self is not
self-created but is an incarnation or enacting of a socially-defined role.
This heroic background is refined by the Greeks in several ways, as by the fifth century B.C. it is possible to disagree about what is just (to Homer, justice was equivalent to what is in harmony with the prevailing order; later, you could ask the question “is what is in harmony with the prevailing order also just?”).
The tragedians (Sophocles in particular) focus on what happens when the moral system fails to cohere, producing contradictions.
A person has two contradictory ethical obligations that cannot be reconciled and the tragedy that results is just that there is no right way to proceed (for instance: my obligation arising from my role as a sister and my obligation arising from my role as the subject of a king come into conflict).
The sophists insist that virtues are relative, and the right way to proceed is whatever gets you what you’re after.
Plato, and later Aristotle, hope to show that the virtues don’t actually conflict and aren’t as flimsy as the sophists would have it.
From here, MacIntyre gives a recap of The Nicomachean Ethics, which, if you’ve been paying attention around here for the past few months, you shouldn’t need.
He says that this ethics tightly links moral virtue and practical intelligence, such that in the Aristotelian view, there is no place for actors like a fool whose heart is in the right place or a bureaucratic manager who is efficient at matching means to ends without care for what the ends are.
But there are problems with trying to bring Aristotle’s ethics into the modern era.
For one thing, Aristotle’s ethics requires a telos for human beings, but his idea of this telos was based on his now-ridiculous-seeming “metaphysical biology.” Also, if Aristotle’s virtues were closely tied to his particular society and to the roles available in it (as we have learned such virtues must be), how can these be relevant to us in our very different society today?
Furthermore, Aristotle views human life as perfectible — he thinks we can ultimately remove the conflicts from it (these conflicts are flaws); MacIntyre thinks it’s more likely that conflicts are more basic, and, like the tragedians concluded, are unavoidable and, well, tragic.
In the Middle-Ages, a fragmentary Aristotelian scheme of virtues was rediscovered, but interpreted through a filter of Christianity — one which was itself influenced by the stoic notion of virtue as a singular thing, detached from telos.
In this view, morally-right acting is solely a matter of will, and the results of the action and whatever virtues contribute to the action are incidental.
There is also an emphasis on the divine law, which is universal (not embedded in the polis or in some particular society).
Secular law had by this time lost any plausible connection to morality — it was no longer an expression of the desires of the polis, but the imposition of an empire.
By the 17th–18th centuries, virtues had lost their coherence altogether, and had come to be understood as a variety of altruism that we call upon to subdue our natural egoism in order to get along with each other.
This would have made no sense to Aristotle, who thought of the virtues as being motivated by self-love and as being at the same time inherently supportive of friendship and community.
Virtues also became mere inclinations to conform to moral laws, and, finally, got reduced from virtues to virtue, as in the stoic viewpoint.
The last great representative of the classical tradition of the virtues in
Western culture was, MacIntyre says,
Jane Austen, who did
this by recreating something akin to the Greek city-state in a fictional
upper-class family milieu.
Healthy, undecayed accounts of virtue have three things in common: a concept of practice, an idea of the narrative order of human life, and a moral tradition that develops out of these.
By “practice,” MacIntyre means some sort of occupation or activity that is
deliberate and well-defined and traditional at least to the extent where it
can involve internal goods — that is, rewards that exist only within
the practice itself and not in terms of what the practice enables you to gain
outside of it. For example, if you play chess well, the reward you get is the
internal good of having played a good chess game; if you are playing in order
to win a trophy, you are playing for the external good of the trophy, not the
internal good of playing well.
External goods are more zero-sum, more the objects of competition.
Internal goods are more about personal excellence; when we succeed in attaining internal goods, this tends not to detract from the good of those around us but to enhance them.
MacIntyre says that a virtue is that which enables us to achieve internal goods.
Practices are embodied in traditions that are kept alive by institutions. But
institutions are themselves focused on external goods. It is the
virtues that keep practices from being corrupted by their institutions
(particularly the virtues of justice, courage, and truthfulness). This doesn’t
mean that all practices are good. Nor does it mean that any practice and
associated set of virtues is as good as any other (for that would lead us back
to the same problem as our current catastrophe). When you see that life has a
telos and therefore there is a practice of life, you see
that life itself has its virtues — you can extrapolate from your idea of the
internal rewards of a practice to the idea of The Good in life as a whole. In
this way the idea of a practice and the understanding of the narrative nature
of human life lead to the development of a coherent moral tradition.
The modern view of life makes this difficult.
Life is divided into stages and further into roles (“work-life” and “home-life” for instance), and we are encouraged to view behaviors atomistically rather than seeing our lives as unified and ourselves as engaged in large-scale narratives.
But human activity is intelligible and our actions are
within a narrative context of history and goals. An action isn’t just part of
a narrative but is part of many narratives from many points of view.
These narratives are unpredictable (what happens next?) but that
doesn’t mean they lack telos or that the
telos is merely retrospectively assigned. The only way I can
answer the question “what am I to do?” is if I can answer the question “what
stories am I a part of?”
The way I read this is that when you ask yourself whether or not you are behaving ethically right, you are trying to justify yourself.
You justify yourself by accounting for your behavior, that is to say, telling its story, putting it in a narrative context complete with its telos.
By doing this you create a context in which the virtues will shine forth as the sort of excellences of character that advance you to your telos.
MacIntyre says that the quest is a form of narrative in which the
character of the protagonist and his telos become more
sharply defined over time. You start off with a vague idea of The Good, and
your experiences over the course of the quest make it clearer what The Good
must be. The virtues are what equip us for success in the quest.
But your narrative, whatever it is, doesn’t start from a blank slate.
You start in a social context that may equip you with obligations, debts, and expectations of various sorts right from the get-go.
You cannot define yourself independently of these, though you have the choice of defining yourself either in agreement with or in rebellion against any of it.
We are all protagonists of the tragic variety, in that we will inevitably encounter irreconcilable ethical obligations.
That said, though we cannot solve the dilemmas we encounter, we can navigate them more or less skillfully.
The concept of virtue MacIntyre has described was destroyed, he says, by the
cult of bureaucratic individualism that emerged from
the
enlightenment. Employees, for example, do not typically engage in a
practice associated with internal goods (they are motivated by salary or other
external goods); the typical modern person is not a practitioner but a
spectator/consumer, engaged in what MacIntyre calls “institutional
acquisitiveness” or “aesthetic consumption”
(consumerism, I think
they call it these days).
Today, people in our culture are unable to weigh conflicting claims of justice because they are inherently incommensurable. John Rawls and Robert Nozick, for example, represent sophisticated philosophical justifications of something akin to popular quasi-socialist liberal and property-rights libertarian perspectives, respectively.
MacIntyre notes that even if you accept either or both of their arguments as valid, this resolves nothing, since it is their premises that are incompatible.
(Interestingly, neither Rawls nor Nozick relies on the concept of
desert, which
is central in the popular versions of justice they are trying to
provide philosophical support for. MacIntyre says that this is because desert
requires a preexisting social context in order to make sense, and the thought
experiments that Rawls and Nozick rely on assume atomistic individuals without
preexisting communities or agreements on what is good. The popular notion of
desert, MacIntyre says, is yet another remnant of premodern justice that
shines through the cracks left after the catastrophe.)
Because there is no common ground on which disagreements about justice and morality can be argued, “modern politics is civil war carried on by other means” — nothing but power masked by rhetoric.
But this is not because Nietzsche has disproved morality.
He successfully defeated the various enlightenment projects of justifying morality, but he left the Aristotelian ethical framework unscathed.
The virtue tradition implies a rejection of the primacy of market values, the
cult of bureaucratic individualism, and acquisitiveness. It indicts the modern
political order (perhaps government in the abstract can be justified, but no
existing government can).
What to do about it?
Our task in this post-catastrophe world, MacIntyre says, is to construct “local forms of community within which civility and the intellectual and moral life can be sustained through the new dark ages which are already upon us.
And if the tradition of the virtues was able to survive the horrors of the last dark ages, we are not entirely without grounds for hope.
This time however the barbarians are not waiting beyond the frontiers; they have already been governing us for quite some time.”
At Wendy McElroy’s suggestion I read William Wollaston’s The Religion of Nature Delineated.
It is at times brilliant and ahead of its time, at times utterly daft and pedestrian.
As a writer, Wollaston is much more straightforward and easy-to-read than many of his 18th century contemporaries, and even when he goes astray he often does so in interesting ways.
His goal in the book is to try to discern ethical truths solely by combining observations about the natural world with rational deductions from these observations — to see if he can derive a sort of universal, baseline religion without the aid of divine revelation but merely by drawing logical conclusions from the available facts.
What sort of religion might you come up with if you had no assistance from God or his prophets other than the light of reason, the evidence of the senses, and a steadfast regard for truth?
Religion, to Wollaston, is synonymous with ethics.
The science of categorizing human acts into the categories of good, evil, or indifferent is the basis of religion.
He acknowledges the many attempts to formulate a rational rule to govern this categorization, and that these attempts have failed, but he asserts that such a rule must exist, and, furthermore, that he has discovered it.
The opening chapter of his book, probably the most interesting one, gives his rule and the reasoning behind it.
It goes a little something like this:
All acts that can be categorized as good or evil must be acts of an intelligent and free agent, capable of choosing or not choosing the act.
Propositions are true if what they express conforms to how things actually are.
A true proposition may be denied either by words or by deeds.
By deeds, I don’t just mean language-like gestures: sign language, pantomime, body language, and the like.
“There are many acts of other kinds, such as constitute the character of a man’s conduct in life, which have in nature, and to imply some proposition, as plainly to be understood as if it was declared in words.”
For example, if a company of soldiers attacks another company, they are by virtue of their attack stating the proposition that the other company is their enemies, which may be a true or false proposition.
Or, if you promise to do A but instead do B, you are by the very act of doing B instead of A denying the truth of your earlier promise.
This does not mean that only those actions that actually communicate something to someone else, or that are theoretically intelligible by someone else, are those that deny propositions.
In the privacy of your home, when you reach for the salt-shaker, you are asserting the proposition: this food isn’t salty enough yet.
Some act-statements, like speech-statements, may be conventional (for example, in some religions, putting on head covering is a sign of reverence; in others, taking off your hat means much the same thing).
Other act-statements are more universal and can said to be natural in a way that words never can be because words are always particular to some language.
“Whoever acts as if things were so, or not so, doth by his acts declare that they are so, or not so, as plainly as he could by words, and with more reality.
And if things are otherwise, his acts contradict those propositions which assert them to be as they are.”
No act that contradicts a true proposition can be right.
False propositions are wrong, so acts that assert them cannot be right.
True propositions express the actual relationship between a subject and an attribute of that subject.
An act that denies this relationship denies reality and is therefore wrong, against nature/reality.
If there is an omnipotent Creator-God, then to deny what is actually true is to deny what God has deliberately called into being.
This is not to say that we should be fatalistically blasé in the face of an evil act, for instance, but that in such a case we should acknowledge as being a true proposition that an evil act occurred.
There are eternal truths that seem to be part of the Divine intention, like “every thing is what it is; that which is done cannot be undone,” and to deny any particular truth that fits this pattern is also to deny the eternal truth itself, which is in effect to deny God.
To deny anything to be true that is in fact true, and that an omniscient God therefore knows to be true, is also to put yourself in opposition to God.
To deny what is true in any instance is to embrace absurdity and to put truth and falsity, good and bad, and knowledge of any sort out of reach.
To deny what is true is to transgress against reason, “the great law of our nature.”
Acts of omission as well as those of commission can be assertions or denials of propositions.
This requires a bit more subtlety to deal with, but, for example, you do not necessarily deny that The Religion of Nature Delineated is an interesting book by not personally being interested enough to read it, but you do deny that everyone ought to read some Shakespeare if you don’t bother to read any yourself.
If you don’t read anything at all, you deny that reading is valuable, or that the value it gives is important, or some proposition of the sort.
Certain truths seem to imply certain actions: if I am rich, and there are poor, were I never to be charitable I would be in a way denying the truth of wealth and poverty by not taking the obvious step such things imply.
If I neglect to help someone in dire need when I am the best or only person able to help, I am making an assertion about myself, that person, the straits that person is in, human nature, and so forth.
To judge rightly what a thing is, all of those attributes of the thing that are capable of being denied must be taken into account.
For example, if a thief rides off on another man’s horse, the thief isn’t denying that it’s a horse by doing this, but that the horse was another man’s property.
The thief’s actions imply certain assertions about the horse (I can do with it what I please, it’s a horse, it’s safe to ride) but don’t imply anything about others (it’s a filly, it’s mottled brown, it was born in Kentucky).
Truths are always consistent with one another, so you won’t ever find yourself in a situation in which you must deny one truth in order to affirm another.
What if you make a promise that you are later unable to keep because of some other obligation?
“It is not in man’s power to promise absolutely.
He can only promise as one who may be disabled by the weight and incombency of truths not then existing.”
When an act would be wrong, forbearing that act is right; when the omission of an act would be wrong, doing that act must be right.
Moral good and evil are coincident with right and wrong.
Acts of omission and of commission that have the effect of denying what is true are morally evil.
Their opposites are good.
Acts that have no propositional content are indifferent.
Denying any truth is evil, but some such denials are worse than others.
All sins are not equal.
For instance, it is worse to deprive someone of an estate than of a book, even though in both cases you are denying the truth of ownership: the estate might be worth 10,000× the book, in which case the evil is also 10,000× greater.
(He tries to justify this by saying that the owner’s valuation of the property is somehow part of the truth statement that the thief is denying, which I think is probably incorrect.
The thief isn’t saying anything about the value of the property to the owner by stealing it, necessarily.)
The quantity of evil/guilt involves “the importance and number of truth violated.”
Good actions, that is, acts that serve as true propositions, are also good in degrees, by inverting the evil that would be the result of their omission (or, I suppose, their commission in the case of good deeds of omission, but that seems to lead into a thicket: aren’t I just about always failing to commit a near infinite number of possible sins?)
Though some deny that there is any such thing as good and evil, indeed there is just as there is a difference between true and false.
Indeed: they resolve to the same thing.
There have been many attempts to find a criterion or rule for distinguishing good things from evil ones, or some ultimate end that serves as the criteria by which good and evil acts can be distinguished, but these have all either failed, or are incomplete, or are circular tautologies, or eventually just reduce in practice to this rule I have proposed.
(Here he reviews several such attempts.)
The natural existence of good and evil implies natural religion.
Religion is “nothing else but an obligation to do… what ought not to be omitted, and to forbear what ought not to be done.”
“[E]very intelligent, active, and free being should so behave himself, as by no act to contradict truth; or, that he should treat every thing as being what it is.”
From here, Wollaston answers some possible objections to his scheme, most of which are the result of misunderstandings of what he’s getting at.
He slips up, I think, when he discusses the case of whether or not it would be a wrong denial-of-truth to refuse to tell an enraged murderer where his prospective victim is hiding.
Among his answers here is that “no one can tell, in strict speaking, where another is, if he is not within his view.
Therefore you may truly deny that you know where the man is.”
This seems to subvert his scheme by hinting that you can behave deceptively while holding on to the truth verbally and legalistically and thereby stay on the straight and narrow.
In general, his answer to this objection seems to rely less on the scheme he’s introduced and more on ordinary folk ethics, which seems odd to me, since I don’t think this objection is particularly threatening to his scheme.
Wollaston also says that some truth-denying sins are worse than others.
Some are so minor as to be “evanescent or almost nothing.”
Furthermore, it is only those truths that have some reference to other living things that we really must respect.
If we don’t treat a television as a television but instead treat it as a target at a shooting range, we don’t commit a sin against the truth (as we would if we treat it as our television when it actually belongs to someone else).
To me, this seems an important qualification tacked carelessly onto Wollaston’s scheme, and weakens the original justification for it, which was that a denial of truth as such was a denial of truth as an aspect of God and therefore a denial of God, without any regard for whether that truth had some relation to other living things.
That concludes the first chapter.
Chapter two concerns happiness.
Wollaston agrees with Aristotle that happiness is best measured over the sum of a person’s life rather than in any particular time-slice.
He also asserts that to make oneself happy is the duty of every intelligent being, and that we must take this truth about intelligent beings into account in our dealings with others.
Furthermore, nothing that denies truth can be productive of the true and ultimate happiness of any being; neither can the practice of truth make any being unhappy (in this life-wide sense of happiness).
This bold assertion he bases on his understanding of the nature of God (which he’ll expand on later): nobody has the power to increase his happiness by setting his will above the evident will of God, and, also, it would be absurd to think that God would be so sadistic or defective as to punish people for conforming to His will.
Because of this, our duty to make ourselves happy and our duty to conform in word and deed to the truth amount to the same thing, and this is our true religion.
Chapter three concerns reason and epistemology.
If we cannot actually know the difference between true and false, or at least have some good heuristics, then all of Wollaston’s project is for naught.
He starts by giving an interesting and sophisticated description of how sense qualia and certain ideas and relationships are both examples of immediate mental data.
These ideas/qualia as such are irrefutable data that we can use as axioms. Wollaston also asserts, less rigorously, that reason can in fact obtain new truths for us (if not, what else is it for?).
The practice of reason is another term for what is also called conformity to truth or the pursuit of true happiness, that is, the true natural religion.
Each person must be his own judge of truth: “to demand another man’s assent to any thing without conveying into his mind such reasons as may produce a sense of the truth of it, is to erect a tyranny over his understanding and to demand a tribute which it is not possible for him to pay.”
There are also things we can’t determine the truth of, but there may be various ways in which we can get a probable truth, and he discusses several such heuristics, for instance, which sorts of authorities to trust.
In such cases, you’re as obligated to conform to the probability as in certain cases you are obligated to conform to the truth: you put your money down on the best odds, even though you can’t know how the dice will roll ahead of time.
Chapter four concerns the free will problem.
Is it even possible for people to conform to the truth?
Wollaston acknowledges that people are not completely in control of their actions, and that you can only be morally obligated to do what you are in fact capable of doing.
You are obligated to conform with truth only so far as your faculties, powers, and opportunities allow, and to the extent that the truth is discernible by you.
That said, don’t act like this is an available cop-out.
You must endeavor “in earnest… heartily; not stifling [your] own conscience, not dissembling, suppressing, or neglecting [your] own powers.”
Wollaston thinks that the free will problem comes up in ethical philosophy as a sort of dodge by people who are hoping for some sort of excuse for not taking ethical problems seriously.
If you were told that a great reward was waiting for you in the next room if you were just to go and retrieve it, you wouldn’t waste time discoursing about whether or not you had the free will necessary to undertake such a task — you’d just get up and go.
But in the realm of ethics, people for some reason feel obligated to dive into the free-will labyrinth rather than just staying on the straight and narrow path to what they know is best.
In chapter five, Wollaston decides to prove the existence of God and describe His nature.
It’s your standard first cause argument (every effect has a cause stretching back through time, but there must have been some original uncaused cause to set this all in motion) combined with the argument from design (isn’t the universe amazing and don’t we see evidence of God’s order and benevolence everywhere?).
Wollaston also shares some thoughts on the compatibility of the divine regulation of the universe and of divine omniscience with free will; whether petitioning an omniscient God with prayer makes any sense; what God might have had in mind by introducing free will into His creation; whether God might from time to time rescind our free will to set us on a particular course; why it is that God seems sometimes to reward the wicked and punish the good; and how it is that we have immaterial souls planted in us by God.
To the certain relief of his publisher, Wollaston discovers that the truths about God that any heathen could discover by diligently applying reason to those facts and relations immediately available to our minds conform remarkably well to contemporary Christian worship: we should feel gratitude to our creator, and express this in prayer; we should eschew idolatry; we should form into congregations and worship together; and so forth.
In chapter six things get interesting again, as Wollaston derives and maps out what in modern anarcho-libertarian popular writing is called the “non-aggression principle.”
People are distinct individuals, each with certain unique properties.
Each person has by nature the possession of certain things, such as his own life, limbs, labor, and the products thereof.
That is to say that basic property rights are inherent in the state of nature and don’t require government or custom to come into being.
Whatever is inconsistent with the general peace & welfare of mankind is inconsistent with the laws of human nature and therefore wrong.
The right laws for a society are those that produce the greatest happiness for the greatest number.
Reason respects cases, not persons, so something that would be true for person A with respect to person B would also be true for B with respect to A if the case were inverted.
In a state of nature, people are equal in terms of dominion (with the exception of the natural dominion parents have over their children).
Power does not confer right — if it did, it could confer the right to anything, including denial of the truth, which we’ve already proven to be wrong.
“No man can have a right to begin to interrupt the happiness of another.”
However, you do have the right to defend yourself, to recover what is stolen from you, or to make reprisals against those who have aggressed against you (to recover the equivalent of whatever you have lost by the injustice).
To have a right to anything means also that you have the right to defend your possession of that thing.
Alas, his first justification for this is that each of us has a natural capability and instinct for self-preservation, and that it would be absurd for us to have such a thing and not be allowed to use it.
It seems to me like this same logic could be used to justify aggression.
Initial property rights are established by first possession or by something being the product of one’s own labor, and last until they are voluntarily relinquished by the possessor.
Stolen property, if it is never reclaimed, may eventually lose its taint as it is passed from hand to hand or generation to generation, so it is not necessary to be able to trace every possession back to a first legitimate owner.
A property right may be transferred by compact or donation.
Among the rights a person has by virtue of ownership is the right to dispose of property in this way, and both the giver and the receiver are acting within their rights.
Trade is mutually beneficial and commerce is a social good.
Therefore: property is founded in nature and truth.
If you don’t dispose of your property by compact or donation, it is yours until you die.
If someone else uses your property without your consent, they are in effect denying the truth of your ownership, in violation of the principles of chapter 1.
If something is your property this means exactly that you have the sole right of using it and disposing of it.
If you use something or dispose of it, you are simultaneously declaring the proposition that it belongs to you.
(Borrowing or renting something is a special case, in which you declare that the thing is yours for the time allowed without doing violence to the truth.)
Injustice means usurping or invading the property of another; justice means quietly permitting to everyone what is theirs.
To not do violence to the truth you must avoid injustice.
Injustice is wrong and evil.
To carelessly cause suffering in others, or to delight in the suffering of others, is cruel.
To be insensitive to the suffering of others is unmerciful.
Mercy and humanity are the opposites of these.
Those who religiously regard truth and nature will, in addition to being just, also be merciful and humane, these things being right.
Let me reiterate that.
Therefore: murder or injury (not in self-defense), robbery, stealing, cheating, betraying, defamation, detraction, defiling the bed of another man, and so forth, as well as tendencies to these things, are heinous crimes (tendencies include things like envy, malice, and the like).
The value of something (for instance, when calculating compensation for injury) is determined by how the rightful owner values it, not by some objective standard and certainly not by the standard of the person who behaves unjustly with respect to it.
A crime done in secret (for instance, to sleep with a man’s wife behind his back) is still an injury and a violation of the truth.
Another interesting thing in this section is that Wollaston seems to anticipate Kant’s categorical imperative, for instance when he says that a person who breaks a promise “denies and sins against truth; does what it can never be for the good of the world should become an universal practice…” (Wollaston died .)
Most of what Wollaston concluded in this chapter would be simpatico with modern anarcho-capitalists and libertarians, though many would cringe at his attempts to find a utilitarian grounding for his scheme, and the objectivists would quibble at the altruism involved in Wollaston’s mandate of mercy.
But in the following chapter, Wollaston reintroduces and justifies government, though he does this along classical liberal lines that probably wouldn’t leave all of the modern fans of the previous chapter behind:
Man is a social animal.
Even if there were not many advantages to living socially, as individuals we would inevitably come up against other people.
Disputes are inevitable.
There will be vicious and ambitious people who will strive to become more powerful and thereby more troublesome to the rest of us.
It is natural, therefore, that good people will form local alliances of mutual support and defense.
The purpose of society is the common welfare of those in it.
People enter into society for that purpose, which implies certain rules or laws according to which they agree to be governed.
This means that they must settle on certain areas of unanimous consent, certain methods for resolving disputes, a system of punishments and deterrents to discourage offenses, and on a method of protecting the alliance from outside attack.
Such laws must be consistent with natural justice in order to be in harmony with truth and thereby not evil.
(Like Robert Nozick, Wollaston believes that a state can naturally emerge from anarchy without violating natural rights along the way.)
A society with laws implies a hierarchy, with governors and governed, judges, magistrates, and the like.
This seems to rule out anarchy, though Wollaston says that “if the society has none [no executors of the law, or no laws, it’s not exactly clear what he means], it is indeed no society, or not such a one as is the subject of this proposition” so maybe he’s leaving open the possibility.
A person may relinquish some of his natural rights and put himself under the control of laws and governors in order to gain the protection of being in a law-governed society.
This is a form of contractual exchange, in which a person gives up something and gets something the person feels is more valuable in exchange, and so this is no violation of the truth as laid out in the previous chapter.
(Indeed it would be a violation of the truth not to make such an advantageous exchange.)
This exchange, says Wollaston, may either be explicit or implicit.
If you take advantage of those privileges that are not your natural rights but are only available to you as a citizen of a commonwealth, you implicitly own allegiance to the laws that go along with it, even if you have not explicitly taken an oath or what have you.
Merely accepting the protection of a state, or choosing to live within its borders, is an implicit acceptance of its laws.
This does real damage to the scheme Wollaston set up in the previous chapter, in which he said that the value of something is set by the rightful possessor of it, and that only the rightful possessor has the right to use or dispose of it.
This modification reminds me of the people who set up shop at road medians, who, when you’re stopped at a red light, wash your windshield without asking you if you want their service, and then act as though you owe them payment for a service you never requested.
Once you become a member of a society, you need to respect not only the natural rights of the people in it (as described in the previous chapter), but any conventional or legal rights that the society establishes: for instance, their titles to property, or the privilege of the state to resolve disputes (rather than individual initiative to seek redress), or subordination to legal authority.
When the law is silent, or impotent, people retain their natural rights, and should behave as described in the previous chapter.
If the law is contrary to natural justice, “one of them must give way; and it is easy to discern, which ought to do it.”
Societies established like the ones described in this chapter have a right to defend themselves against other societies.
“War may lawfully be waged in defense and for the security of a society, its members and territories, or for reparation of injuries.”
This is deliberately parallel to his formulation of an individual right in the state of nature.
Nations with respect to other nations are situated like individuals with respect to other individuals in the absence of a state (at least “so far as they have not limited themselves by leagues and alliances.”)
Another way of looking at this is that a nation may defend collectively the agglomerated individual rights of its citizens against the unjust aggression of an outside individual or group of individuals under the very same principles that individuals in the state of nature can defend their rights against one another.
Chapter eight concerns families and kinship: the nature of marriage, the responsibility of parents for children, the authority of parents over children — “I have designedly forborn to mention that authority of a husband over his wife, which is usually given to him, not only by private writers, but even by laws; because I think it has been carried much too high.
I would have them live so far upon the level, as (according to my constant lesson) to be governed both by reason” — the debt of gratitude and other duties children owe parents, and the justification for us not treating all men as brothers but actually treating our kin better than everyone else.
Absolute maxims about individual liberty favored by some libertarian and anarchist thinkers often seem to run aground on the parent/child relationship.
By what right do I as a parent interfere with my child’s liberty to run out into traffic?
Well, it’s not hard to come up with some good reasons, but it can be hard to shoehorn them in alongside certain confidently-asserted principles about liberty.
So it’s a sign that Wollaston takes the subject seriously that he includes this chapter.
He also tries to guard against the monarchist gambit of sneaking tyranny in through this gap by analogizing the relationship of a king to subjects to that of a parent to children.
Wollaston says this won’t fly for a number of reasons.
The final chapter concerns human nature.
It reiterates our duty to devote ourselves to truth, reason, and virtue (three names for the same thing).
Some of the self-facing virtues are prudence, temperance, chastity, and frugality, but Wollaston is quick to stress that these are not virtues of self-denial so much as of rational self-interest.
Chastity, for instance, is not the avoidance of sex, or of the pleasure from sex, but it’s knowing how best to fit sexual pleasure into our lives in a way that is compatible with our long-term goals and with other virtues.
Virtue, says Wollaston, tends to lead to happiness; vice to unhappiness.
It’s not as though “virtue can make a man happy upon a rack” or dissolve all the misfortunes we may encounter, but in any situation, the most advantageous act and the virtuous act coincide (vice can’t make you happy on a rack either).
Wollaston goes on at great length to speculate on the nature of the soul (which he describes at first in a way that we might use the term “mind” for).
He rejects three monist hypotheses to resolve the mind-body problem: 1) that all matter thinks, 2) that certain configurations or motions of matter generate thought, 3) that thinking is an epiphenomenon of some sort that accompanies certain configurations of matter.
Instead, he asserts that thinking is a property of some special, non-material substance that God attaches to some sort of diaphanous interface in our brains that allows it to receive impressions from the physical world and to direct our bodies.
This substance is the soul, and, it being non-material, we have no reason to expect that it expires when the body it is attached to dies.
From here, Wollaston makes a number of ill-supported speculations about the nature of the soul.
Worst, he reasons that there must be an afterlife because he has proven that there is a just and reasonable God, and yet on earth there is so much cruelty and injustice and disorder, that only a just and harmonious afterlife could possibly balance the scales and be compatible with God’s nature.
Alas, the proof of God he relies on as one of the axioms of this argument itself proceeded from the observation that the universe was so orderly and benevolent that it must be the creation of a just and wise God.
So Wollaston has to utterly contradict himself to try and prove his point.
In all, once he gets past some interesting and well-considered thoughts on the mind/body problem, the rest of this chapter in which he gives his speculations about the nature of God, the destiny of the soul, and so forth are pretty worthless: just his own opinion of how he would organize the universe were he a just, omniscient, and omnipotent creator.
He even uses that most desperate gambit of saying that even if the immortality of the soul cannot be demonstrated, “yet it is certain the contrary cannot”!
From which he slides into Pascal’s Wager.
(His version is slightly improved by his assertion that a virtuous life that is to our advantage from the standpoint of eternity also happens to be to our advantage from the standpoint of our mortal lives.)
His concluding advice: “let our conversation in this world, so far as we are concerned, and able, be such as acknowledges every thing to be what it is (what it is in itself, and what with regard to us, to other beings, to causes, circumstances, consequences): that is, let us by no act deny any thing to be true, which is true: that is, let us act according to reason: and that is, let us act according to the law of our nature.”
In , The Religion of Nature Delineated was released as a free (as in speech, and as in beer) ebook, with a number of readability improvements for the benefit of today’s reader.
You can download it from this link.
If you’ve heard of Adam Smith, it’s probably because of his book The Wealth of Nations, which launched the study of economics, or his concept of “the invisible hand” by which individuals, each looking out only for their own personal gain, end up unwittingly contributing to the prosperity of society as a whole.
I have not read The Wealth of Nations, but I’m currently reading Smith’s earlier book, The Theory of Moral Sentiments.
Today I’ll share some of my thoughts on volume one of that book, including the surprising context of his “invisible hand” quote.
When people argue about the application of moral values, usually implicit in their arguments is the theory that morality either arises from a system or that it ought to be systematized.
In these arguments, showing that some ethical assertion or other is unsystematic or is systematically inconsistent seems equivalent to showing it to be disproven or wrong.
Therefore much ethical philosophy has involved systematizing morality in various ways and then trying to test the soundness of the resulting systems.
“Experimental” ethical philosophy takes a different tack: taking human moral judgment as a pre-systematization given and trying to describe its contours rather than force it into a rationally-invented mold.
The Theory of Moral Sentiments is in this camp, though Smith’s “experimentation” isn’t very rigorous — mostly amounting to introspection and examination of the opinions of well-considered men of his time, place, and class.
Anyone writing a book of experimental ethics today would spend a little time writing a prelude like this one that explains the difference in outlook and goals that motivates such a project and distinguishes it from most other ethical philosophy.
Smith, though — curiously — just jumps in and starts describing human moral judgment without any such throat-clearing.
It is not until part two of the book, in a footnote that looks as though it were added to respond to critics who misunderstood this very nature of his project, that he makes things explicit:
…[T]he present inquiry is not concerning a matter of right, if I may say so, but concerning a matter of fact.
We are not at present examining upon what principles a perfect being would approve of the punishment of bad actions; but upon what principles so weak and imperfect a creature as man actually and in fact approves of it.…
To Smith, the instinct to make moral judgments, like the instincts that make us hungry or horny, is built-in.
And like those, the acts it prompts us to do tell us something about human nature and about how our creator (or Creator) intends to guide us.
We feel hunger to prompt us to sustain our bodies; we feel lust to prompt us to reproduce.
Our feelings of resentment, gratitude, and other such moral emotions, Smith feels, must also have been implanted in us for the purpose of guiding our behavior toward certain ends.
Rather than assuming the ends ahead of time and then trying to systematize an ethics that conforms to them, wouldn’t it be wiser (Smith feels) to carefully examine these emotions and try to derive these ends from what we find?
In every part of the universe we observe means adjusted with the nicest artifice to the ends which they are intended to produce; and in the mechanism of a plant, or animal body, admire how every thing is contrived for advancing the two great purposes of nature, the support of the individual, and the propagation of the species.
But in these, and in all such objects, we still distinguish the efficient from the final cause of their several motions and organizations.
The digestion of the food, the circulation of the blood, and the secretion of the several juices which are drawn from it, are operations all of them necessary for the great purposes of animal life.
Yet we never endeavour to account for them from those purposes as from their efficient causes, nor imagine that the blood circulates, or that the food digests of its own accord, and with a view or intention to the purposes of circulation or digestion.
… But though, in accounting for the operations of bodies, we never fail to distinguish in this manner the efficient from the final cause, in accounting for those of the mind we are very apt to confound these two different things with one another.
When by natural principles we are led to advance those ends, which a refined and enlightened reason would recommend to us, we are very apt to impute to that reason, as to their efficient cause, the sentiments and actions by which we advance those ends, and to imagine that to be the wisdom of man, which in reality is the wisdom of God.
Our moral emotions serve us.
They sustain us and help us to propagate by prompting us to actions that strengthen useful friendships and discourage human enemies, predators & parasites.
For example, our acts and declarations of gratitude, prompted by our moral emotions, further encourage those who have shown themselves to be able & inclined to do us useful service.
Smith, — remarkably, in — had written a book of evolutionary psychology.
He didn’t know that was what he was doing, of course (Darwin’s On the Origin of Species was still ), but his book is agnostic enough about the nature of this creator who “implanted the seeds of [moral emotion] in the human breast” — sometimes it is “Nature,” other times “the author of nature,” other times “God” or “the Deity” — that it is not particularly awkward to fill in the blank today, now that we know the answer.
Smith at times comes awfully close to this himself, as for instance when he describes the different emotional bonds that connect parents and children:
Nature, for the wisest purposes, has rendered in most men, perhaps in all men, parental tenderness a much stronger affection than filial piety.
The continuance and propagation of the species depend altogether upon the former, and not upon the latter.
The edition I got from the library was published by Regnery Publishing for the “Conservative Leadership Series” of the “Conservative Book Club.”
It’s not a very good advertisement for that brand, being riddled with typographical errors, misspellings (applause ringing in our “cars,” for instance), missing words, and other awkwardnesses that demonstrate that optical character recognition software is no substitute for a dutiful editor.
I suspect that a book club selection like this is meant more for ostentatious display than for reading, however, so perhaps such niceties are superfluous.
In some ways, Adam Smith is a sensible choice for the conservative pantheon.
His free-trade / free-market viewpoints, once considered de rigueur for good liberals, are now mostly honored (and mostly in the breach) by American conservatives.
But this book doesn’t seem to harmonize well with contemporary American conservativism: Moral descriptivism is far too godless.
I expect most Conservative Book Club members would be horrified if their children were being taught by some liberal professor about how morality was implanted in us by nature to promote the survival of the individual and the propagation of the species, and that you could derive morality from human ethical emotions without any reference to preexisting moral absolutes.
But back to Smith: When I first read Smith’s description of conscience, I was lulled by how sensible it seemed and at first I didn’t notice what an unusual explanation (for its time, anyway) it was.
To Smith, “conscience” isn’t the insight by which we discern good & evil or the nagging voice prompting us to resist temptation, but is instead the faculty by which we simulate the perspective of an impartial observer who observes our own headspace and behavior, using the same criteria we naturally use when judging others.
It is an application of the same, innate judgments we already have access to by virtue of being human, but using a difficult and specialized variety of imagination in which we cast that judgment through a point of view that is not our own and not (as) prejudiced by self-interest.
Because this process is so difficult, especially when our minds are distracted by particularly strong temptations or crisis circumstances of quick change and the need for rapid action, we tend to supplement our consciences by inventing and memorizing heuristics that we can apply to situations so that we can quickly flag those that require conscientious scrutiny.
This process of inventing heuristics, Smith believes, is the source of the ethical philosopher’s suspicion that ethics is or ought to be systematized:
It is thus that the general rules of morality are formed.
They are ultimately founded upon experience of what, in particular instances, our moral faculties, our natural sense of merit and propriety, approve, or disapprove of.
We do not originally approve or condemn particular actions because, upon examination, they appear to be agreeable or inconsistent with a certain general rule.
The general rule, on the contrary, is formed by finding from experience that all actions of a certain kind, or circumstanced in a certain manner, are approved or disapproved of.
When these general rules, indeed, have been formed, when they are universally acknowledged and established by the concurring sentiments of mankind, we frequently appeal to them as to the standards of judgment, in debating concerning the degree of praise or blame that is due to certain actions of a complicated and dubious nature.
They are upon these occasions commonly cited as the ultimate foundations of what is just and unjust in human conduct; and this circumstance seems to have misled several very eminent authors to draw up their systems in such a manner as if they had supposed that the original judgments of mankind with regard to right and wrong were formed like the decisions of a court of judicatory, by considering first the general rule, and then, secondly, whether the particular action under consideration fell properly within its comprehension.
The book has some flaws.
For one thing, Smith is wordy and repetitive.
He seems to think if a point is worth making, it’s worth making three times just to make sure.
I’ve never read a book that cried out more for a Readers’ Digest abridged edition.
But aside from points of style, the major flaw is Smith’s insistence that an examination of human morality is equivalent to an examination of the opinions of well-bred, enlightenment-minded, well-to-do English men of the 18th century.
His curiosity isn’t sufficient to consider other points of view as also being manifestations of human nature, or as anything but inferior versions of the mature morality of his fellows.
Some of his conclusions follow comfortably and obviously from his biased choice of exemplars, and are unconvincing to the modern, more cosmopolitan reader.
But it’s ahead of its time and thought-provoking, and a well-needed perspective on ethical philosophy that ought to be more influential today than it appears to be.
It’s Halloween. Wanna hear something scary? There may be absolutely no
objective standard of moral right and wrong. Good and evil might be entirely
subjective, or merely a social convention, or might even (shudder) be entirely
meaningless and only trick-or-treating in the costume of meaningful concepts.
The status of moral statements, like the idea of free will, is under a
philosophical cloud. Most everyone believes in their heart of hearts that they
have free will, but when you look up close at the philosophical arguments for
and against it, it looks wildly implausible. Similarly, when people argue
about moral values, they almost always are arguing against a background
assumption that some values are just plain right — not conventionally
right, not mere opinions or exhortations, but facts. But this too
looks very implausible on close examination.
In Whatever Happened to Good and Evil? Russ Shafer-Landau tries to rescue moral objectivism (the idea that certain moral judgments are indeed objectively correct or incorrect, always and everywhere, and independently of who utters them or what culture they come from) from a variety of forms of moral skepticism:
nihilism (the idea that moral
judgments are meaningless or refer to nothing at all), moral
relativism (the idea that moral rules are social conventions, like the
rules of grammar or of baseball), and moral subjectivism (the idea
that moral judgments are personal evaluations, like disgust or erotic
attraction, and are only true or false to the extent that they are sincere
or insincere).
Shafer-Landau does this in a peculiar way. Rather than trying to make an
affirmative case for moral objectivism, he instead tries to demolish the case
for the following two propositions:
Some form of moral skepticism has been logically proven.
Any form of moral objectivism can be logically disproven.
This form of logical argument, though, at best only demonstrates that moral objectivism remains logically possible — it doesn’t actually make a case for it being true.
(Though Shafer-Landau has written a larger book, Moral Realism: A Defence, that may make this case:
I don’t know.)
So in part one, he describes a number of arguments for moral skepticism and
shows that they each have weaknesses that make them unable to successfully
win the day. And in part two, he looks at various take-downs of moral
objectivism and shows that they don’t succeed in leaving moral objectivism
without a logical escape route.
He does a pretty good job in part two, though I’m not convinced that he has
successfully attacked the best versions of the best of such arguments. Part
one, though, is a complete mess. Many of his arguments there mostly reduce to
“this argument for moral skepticism must be incorrect because it leads to
conclusions that are incompatible with moral objectivism” — in other words,
assuming what he means to prove.
Moral objectivism is reassuring, intuitive, and allows ordinary moral
discourse to have a point. I often find myself wishing it were true. I’m
pretty sure, though, that it’s incorrect, and after reading this careful
defense from a convinced believer, I’m more sure than before.
I admit I was a little surprised — I think I had associated the Dalai Lama with some of his more foggy-headed, romantic, guru-seeking fans here in California and so I approached his book with preconceptions of it being likely to be a bunch of gauzy platitudes dressed up with Buddhist nomenclature and foisted off as profundity.
Instead, the book was largely methodical and precise, and also refreshingly practical in a way that many modern books on ethics are not.
I recently read his earlier book, Ethics for the New Millennium (), and, alas, it was more along the lines of what I had been afraid Beyond Religion was going to be.
Still, there was some meat on the bone worth chewing on.
The key to Ethics for the New Millennium is the Dalai Lama’s assertion that the way to be happy and content is to develop and expand one’s own compassion.
The purest and most universally-directed altruism is simultaneously the most enlightened self-interest.
Similarly, the key to solving the variety of the world’s problems is for the people directly involved in the problems and their solutions to develop and nurture compassion in themselves — if they do this, the solutions will come of themselves; if they fail to attend to this, then no programs they come up with, however clever, will do the trick.
Because, according to the Dalai Lama, the happiness/suffering continuum is the primary (or even only) human motivator — as people come to understand that their happiness depends on compassion and on the happiness of others, a sort of virtuous cycle will lift all of us up into more rewarding lives.
To me, all of this is suspiciously nice-sounding, as in “wouldn’t it be nice if that were true.”
But do we have any reason to believe that it is true, or are we just inclined to believe it because it sounds comforting?
For example, is it really accurate to say that people are motivated by a one-dimensional happiness/suffering continuum?
Might it not really be the case that human motivations are multi-dimensional, and that these motivations might be pulling us in different directions at once — some towards less suffering and more happiness, and some just the opposite?
People are driven by status and shame, eroticism and disgust, fear and pride, and so many other things besides, and at least some of these seem to map only awkwardly to the happiness/suffering continuum.
And is it really true that by cultivating compassion and empathy and exhibiting altruistic behavior that we inevitably become happier and more content?
This may sound cynical, but I think there may be a confusion of cause and effect here.
I know that when I am being compassionate, empathetic, and altruistic I am also usually happy and content — but might it be that when my own needs are met, when my life overflows with abundance, when I have few worries and cares, then I am most able to concentrate on other people’s needs and take the time to attend to them?
It may be that my happiness and contentment and my compassion and altruism stem from a common precondition of being carefree and satisfied.
(When I put on my amateur sociobiologist’s pith helmet, I get even more cynical about this: conspicuously altruistic acts are a great way of demonstrating fitness to potential mates.
They’re kind of like feathers in a peacock’s tail: “Look at how much surplus I have in my life, that I can spend so much time, energy, and/or money on the lives of other people!
I must be a mighty successful fellow!”)
One thing I thought was interesting was the Dalai Lama’s suggestion that people use something akin to creative visualization to develop compassion.
In a similar way to the way athletes will imagine themselves succeeding in particular athletic feats, and this act of vivid imagination will help to train their minds and bodies to cooperate in actually accomplishing these feats, the Dalai Lama suggests that we can improve our compassion by “sustained reflection on, and familiarization with compassion, through rehearsal and practice”.
Now while generally translated simply as “compassion,” the term nying je has a wealth of meaning that is difficult to convey succinctly… It connotes love, affection, kindness, gentleness, generosity of spirit, and warm-heartedness… [I]t does not imply “pity” as the word compassion may.
There is no sense of condescension.
On the contrary, nying je denotes a feeling of connection with others, reflecting its origins in empathy.…
…[It] is understood as an emotion, [but] it belongs to that category of emotions which have a more developed cognitive component.
Some emotions, such as the revulsion we tend to feel at the sight of blood, are basically instinctual.
Others, such as fear of poverty, have this more developed cognitive component.
We can thus understand nying je in terms of a combination of empathy and reason.
We can think of empathy as the characteristic of a very honest person; reason as that of someone who is very practical.
When the two are put together, the combination is highly effective.
The process of developing nying je and of disciplining those emotions and tendencies that interfere with it, is a life-long one:
This is no easy task, and those who are religiously minded must understand that there is no blessing or initiation — which, if only we could receive it — or any mysterious or magical formula or mantra or ritual — if only we could discover it — that can enable us to achieve transformation instantly.
It comes little by little, just as a building is constructed brick by brick or, as the Tibetan expression has it, an ocean is formed drop by drop.
Also, because, unlike our bodies which soon get sick, old, and worn out, the afflictive [harm-provoking] emotions never age, it is important to realize that dealing with them is a lifelong struggle.
Nor should the reader suppose that what we are talking about here is the mere acquisition of knowledge.
It is not even a question of developing the conviction that may come from such knowledge.
What we are talking about is gaining an experience of virtue through constant practice and familiarization so that it becomes spontaneous.
What we find is that the more we develop concern for others’ well-being, the easier it becomes to act in others’ interests.
As we become habituated to the effort required, so the struggle to sustain it lessens.
Eventually, it will become second nature.
But there are no shortcuts.