Aristotle → Nicomachean Ethics → Book Ⅶ (self-control, and pleasure)

In the opening section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle begins to investigate how people come to behave badly even though they ought to know better.

There are three basic moral states to be avoided, and three good states contrary to those:

bad stateits contrary
vice, intemperance, wickedness virtue, temperance, goodness
incontinence, imperfect self-control, weakness, self-indulgence continence, self-control, self-command, manliness, self-restraint
brutishness, brutality, beastly depravity, ferocity, savagery superhuman virtue, heroic virtue, godlike virtue, heroism, heroic temperament, heroic greatness

These seem to stand in a sort of hierarchy:

  1. Heroic greatness (nearly divine)
  2. Virtue (habitually good)
  3. Self-control (able to develop good habits)
  4. Incontinence (slips into bad actions)
  5. Vice (habitually bad)
  6. Brutishness (nearly subhuman)

First, Aristotle plans to examine self-control. Self-control is associated with endurance and manliness; its contrary, incontinence, is associated with softness and effeminacy. With any luck, we’ll find that this gendered characterization is not essential to Aristotle’s formulation but is just an artifact of the sexist assumptions of his culture.

Aristotle’s method here, as it has been elsewhere, has been to start by looking at the particulars of how people use words and concepts and then try to describe and make consistent the models implicit in these usages — rather than starting with a theoretical model of what the words and concepts should mean and then trying to cram it down onto the vulgate.

So he reviews a set of common opinions about self-control:

  1. Self-control (and endurance) are thought to be good and praiseworthy; incontinence (and softness) bad and blameworthy.
  2. A person with self-control resolves to do something and then does it, while an incontinent person makes resolutions but lacks sticktoitiveness.
  3. The incontinent person is aware that what he or she is doing is bad, but is unable to resist his or her appetites. The person with self control is aware that appetites are tempting but is able to keep his or her rational mind in charge rather than letting appetite take the reins.
  4. People say that temperate people also have self-control and endurance. However, not everyone with self-control is thought of as also temperate. The words “self-indulgent” and “incontinent” are sometimes used interchangeably, other times to mean somewhat different things. There is disagreement as to whether self-control comes in degrees or is something you either have or you don’t.
  5. Some people believe that if you have practical wisdom, you cannot be incontinent; other people think that it’s possible to be practically wise and yet fail to practice self-control.
  6. People are sometimes said to lack self control in regard to things like anger, honor, or gain (not merely in regard to pleasure, as was the case for Temperance/Self-Indulgence, which Aristotle covered in book three).
Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


In the opening section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle interrogated the folk psychology of his day to ask what it had to say about self-control and its lack, and he came up with a list of things that are popularly believed about self-control and some other things on which there doesn’t appear to be any consensus.

In the second section, Aristotle continues this inquiry, in the hopes that he can come up with a coherent concept of self-control that more-or-less agrees with the popular use of the term.

How is it that someone can know the difference between right and wrong in some circumstance, and yet choose the wrong over the right?

Socrates thought this was inherently contradictory: people only make choices by choosing what they believe to be right, so that whenever they choose something wrong they do so because they were factually mistaken about it and incorrectly believed it to be right.

Aristotle says flatly that “this view plainly contradicts the observed facts.” He wants a better explanation. How is it that someone comes to know what the right course of action is and then does something else instead? Does that person change his or her mind? Does some other part of the soul take over the reins from reason and override reason’s choices? Does the knowledge of right and wrong evaporate on contact with certain sensations or temptations? Is the supposed knowledge of right-and-wrong that the incontinent person displays at first actually only an unexamined opinion that doesn’t survive contact with real life?

Some people think that it is some form of prudence or practical wisdom that makes people change their minds at the last minute and choose vice over virtue — sort of a “that virtue looked pretty good until I saw it up close and then I realized I liked the vice better” or da mihi castitatem et continentiam, sed noli modo (Lord, give me chastity and continence, but not right away). Aristotle thinks this is silly. Prudence and incontinence are contradictory, and willingly choosing vice over virtue is never an example of practical wisdom.

Self-control is all about resisting temptation. So to some extent it’s, ironically, in opposition to Temperance. If you’re Temperate, you don’t really have strong temptations to vice — your appetites are good ones, your desires are virtuous ones. For this reason, if you’re Temperate you don’t have strong temptations that need to be resisted, and so you won’t exhibit self-control, or if you do, it will be a perverse sort of self-control that inhibits you from doing things that are good.

Self-control can be mere stubbornness, if the point-of-view you’re valiantly sticking to is a stupid or vicious one. And, on the other side of the coin, it can be praiseworthy to vacillate or change your mind if there is reasonable doubt as to whether your original game plan is virtuous or not.

Sophists have used this to formulate an uncomfortable paradox in which they ask their listeners to agree that someone who is both perfectly foolish and perfectly incontinent is thereby virtuous, since he or she will stupidly decide to do something vicious and then incontinently fail to follow through, doing something virtuous instead.

Someone who deliberately does something vicious is, to some extent, more amenable to change than someone who incontinently flips to viciousness at the last minute in the face of temptation. It’s possible to persuade the former of his or her error, but for the latter no amount of persuasion is going to do the trick.

Finally, as was mentioned in the previous section, some people are said to have or lack self-control about some thing in particular (say, money, regard, power); but there’s also a sense in which we can say some people just plain lack self-control, even though they may not lack self-control in some of these particular areas. What do we mean by this?

This all presents quite a tangle, which Aristotle will attempt to untangle in the coming sections.

I’m curious as to how “hypocrisy” fits in this model. It seems to share some characteristics with incontinence, though maybe mostly with the weak version in which the original, virtuous point of view was more “opinion” than “knowledge.”

Hypocrisy is big in modern popular ethical thought — there’s no gotcha that’s a better gotcha than some “family values” Republican getting caught with his pants down, for instance, and political bloggers are always trying to catch each other making absolute pronouncements on opposite sides of the same issue for partisan reasons. People don’t seem to beware hypocrisy, exactly, as though they thought of it as inherently harmful, but they’re reluctant to be caught in it because it is embarrassing. (This is almost no more than a sport — like photographing celebrities without their make-up on for the tabloids.)

But since Aristotle thinks that politics is an important thing for thoughtful people to engage in, and that the purpose of politics is, in part anyway, to legislate and guide citizens in ethical behavior, it seems that there is a public counterpart to the private weakness that is incontinence, and that would be hypocrisy.

Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


In the third section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle continues to dig into the mysteries of lack of self-control (or, “incontinence” in the Ross translation).

In the previous section, Aristotle noted the various and conflicting philosophical and popular notions about self-control and its absence. In this section he intends to dump the ones that are no good and to pull the remainder together into something coherent and useful.

Among the questions Aristotle thinks need to be addressed are these:

  • When a person fails to exercise self control, is he or she acting wrongly in spite of knowing better, or as an example of not knowing better?
  • If the former, what sort of knowledge is this that seems so feeble in guiding the behavior of the person without self-control?
  • Is self-control domain-specific, that is, does it apply to certain temptations or varieties of temptation and not others, or is it more of a general thing having to do with temptation in general?
  • Are self-control (resisting the temptation of pleasure) and endurance (putting up with pain) two aspects of the same basic character trait, or are they distinct?
  • Is self-control (and its absence) distinguished by the object matter (the things that are so tempting that they cause lack of self-control) or by the attitude of the subject (the way in which these tempting things are pursued), or by some combination of the two?
  • What is the relation between self-control and temperance?

The last question is easy to answer: it’s all in the attitude. The intemperate person gives into temptation because he or she doesn’t see anything wrong in doing so. The incontinent person, on the other hand, gives into temptation despite at least seeming to have had inclinations to the contrary.

Aristotle wants to entertain the idea that there is a sort of in-between state between having knowledge and not having it. He says that people who are asleep, insane, intoxicated, infuriated, carried away by lust, and other such things, can enter states in which their behavior is not influenced in a reasonable way by their knowledge. Incontinence, he says, is probably some sort of mental condition like these.

The fact that incontinent people can articulate the right decisions they should have made and the right reasons for those neglected decisions just means that they know enough to fake it — like “actors on the stage.” They haven’t internalized and identified with the ethics they’ve learned to pantomime — they know the words, but not the music.

What sort of ignorance is someone exhibiting who behaves at one moment as though they knew right from wrong and who nonetheless the next minute does the wrong thing? Aristotle suggests that it is ignorance of particulars, not of universals that is to blame. This is terminology associated with the syllogism:

universal premiseAll men are mortal
particular premiseSocrates is a man
conclusionSocrates is mortal

When carried away by a passion or overwhelmed by temptation, you lose track of the particular. There are two types of premise: subjective and objective. A subjective particular premise might be “I am a man,” while an objective particular premise might be “Socrates is a man.” Aristotle says it stretches credibility to think that you’d lose track of a subjective particular premise, but it’s entirely possible that your vision might get cloudy about objective particular premises.

Our ethical reasoning has, according to Aristotle, this syllogistic form. We have moral codes, in the form of universal premises, and we understand the world around us in terms of particular premises that sometimes lock into one or more of these universal premises and compel us to realize a conclusion, which, in the case of ethical reasoning, should also compel an action (or compel us to desist from an action).

One possibility is that the person without self-control has conflicting universal premises that haven’t been well-integrated. So if, for instance, you have the universals of “eat delicious food at every opportunity” and “don’t take what does not belong to you” and you find a chocolate eclair in the fridge at work, what do you do? On spotting the eclair you form the two particular premises “that eclair does not belong to me” and “that eclair is delicious food” and come to two contradictory conclusions: “don’t take it!” and “eat it!”

Aristotle says that because the “eat it!” case has a sensual desire associated with it, where as the “don’t take it!” case does not, it is that much easier to translate the “eat it!” conclusion into actual action, and so it can win out in the weak person. Somehow, the presumptive conclusion (“eat it”) combined with the sensual desire blinds the incontinent person to the inconvenient facts (“that’s not yours”) that might interfere with the satisfaction of the desire.

I don’t know if I’d restrict this to sensual desire, the way Aristotle does. I think things like fear of social ostracization, lust for power or prestige, anticipation of financial reward, and things like that can be just as blinding. But I’m willing to accept the idea that it is particular premises, not universal ones, that are what get disrupted in the incontinent person.

(You may notice that this seems to have circled around to the idea that incontinence is a variety of ignorance — Socrates’s idea that Aristotle seemed hostile to at first. Aristotle acknowledges this in this section.)

I wish he’d say a bit more (maybe he will) about what happens when two rules of behavior collide like this. The incontinent person says “two rules conflict, telling me to do opposite things? which one will feel better?” Whereas the wiser person says something like “two rules conflict, telling me to do opposite things? which one is more important here, or is there a third rule that governs cases like this, or can I reformulate the rules in a justifiable way so they don’t conflict anymore?”

The debate about tax resistance as it’s conducted by people who aren’t resisters and who disapprove of resistance often resolves into a debate about particular premises: “Taxation is theft.” “No it isn’t.” “If you pay taxes you are complicit in what the government does with the money.” “No you aren’t.” All of this involves jockeying on the playing field of universal ethical premises (“Being robbed is bad and to be avoided” or “Being complicit in mass slaughter, torture, and other such crimes is bad and to be avoided”) in the hopes of compelling (or at least justifying) behavior.

It looks like it’s a stretch to see this as a problem of self-control / continence. Sometimes war tax resisters, for example, will look at other folks in the peace movement and ask, incredulously, “how can you pay to support what you say you oppose?” as though it were a matter of having drawn an obvious conclusion from preexisting premises and uncontrovertable facts and then, incontinently perhaps, disregarding the conclusion. But it seems like something more than simple sensual desire is causing people to reject particular premises like “taxation is theft" or “taxpaying makes you complicit.” There are complex institutions and webs of propaganda designed to justify the opposite conclusions (and it might even be that one or both of those premises are false, in which case rejecting them would be entirely rational).

Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


These NWTRCC National Gatherings are intense. By the end of the day my brain is all mushy and I have to strain to process one more piece of information. The time difference got to me too, a bit. I thought I was clever, booking an early-morning flight so I could get home mid-day and have some time to unwind. I didn’t think that it would mean waking up at 2:30 AM home-time to get to the airport.

While I was in our session on war tax resistance counseling skills training, coincidentally, I got an email from someone seeking war tax resistance counseling who had read my blog and had gone from feeling like tax resistance would be too overwhelming and difficult to feeling hopeful that there would be a method that would be right for her. So the heartwarming glow from the meeting has followed me home to my inbox.

I’m home, hopefully for a good while. I’ve been away more than not lately, and as the lady with the nice shoes says, there’s no place like home. My work-for-a-living work is on an uptick lately, too, but I hope I’ll be able to keep up the pace here at The Picket Line.

Today, more Aristotle!

In the fourth section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle raises and begins to address two additional questions about lack of self-control, or “incontinence”:

  1. Are some people incontinent in general, or do people display incontinence with respect to certain things?
  2. What is the relationship between continence and temperance, and between continence and endurance?

Aristotle says that there are two categories of pleasure that can prompt incontinent behavior: “necessary” pleasures (things like food and sex), and certain other pleasures that are worth pursuing but that people are prone to pursue to excess (things like victory, honor, and wealth).

The pleasures in the first category (and associated pains, like hunger, thirst, and excesses of heat & cold) are the same as those that were the concern of temperance and intemperance (a virtue and vice Aristotle covered in book three). When incontinence is displayed here it is incontinence without qualification — not only a fault but a kind of vice, Aristotle says.

The difference between continence/incontinence and temperance/intemperance is that temperance or intemperance is a choice and a habit of character — an exercise of the will — while incontinence is contrary to choice — a failure of will.

For those pleasures in the second category, however, continence and incontinence is only so with respect to the particular pleasure. Indeed, it is not continence or incontinence proper, but is only given those names by analogy. People who display one of these qualified varieties of incontinence are not vicious but are merely excessive to a fault in pursuit of good things.

I’m not sure why Aristotle distinguishes this from a vice; it seems to me that a habit of character that leads to someone pursuing some good or avoiding some bad excessively would qualify as a vice if in fact it is a fault and “bad and to be avoided” (not just a harmless eccentricity).

Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


In the fifth section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle develops a new categorization scheme to organize the sorts of pleasures that can prompt a lack of self control, including, this time, certain pathological cases.

First, there are those things that are pleasant by nature. Some of these are pleasant without qualification and to any creature capable of feeling them. These correspond to the natural pleasures mentioned in the previous section: things like the discomfort of hunger, and the pleasure of eating; the pleasure of sex; the bodily sensations that lead animals to avoid extremes of temperature and seek out a comfort zone; things of that sort.

Others of these natural pleasures are only pleasant to certain sorts of creatures: there are specifically-human pleasures and pains that other animals do not take part in, and further there are pleasures and pains that only certain sorts of people participate in (not everybody takes pleasure in making art, for instance, or is pained by poorly-made coffee).

The other category of pleasures contains those that are not naturally pleasant but that are pleasant to some people because of some pathology:

  • some physical malady like madness or disease
  • a habit acquired in childhood as a result of trauma or abuse
  • psychopathology, or “brutishness”

In these categories are people who commit savage and difficult-to-understand crimes (your Jeffrey Dahmers and the like), pedophiles, people with obsessive-compulsive disorder, pica, or phobias, and things of that sort. Aristotle says that these things are not really varieties of incontinence but are something else. Those whose lack of self control has natural causes like disease or injury “no one would call incontinent,” while those whose lack of self control comes from “a morbid condition as a result of habit” or from brutishness is exhibiting something “beyond the limits of vice.”

The varieties of pleasure that can lead to lack of self-control, from R.W. Browne’s The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle ().

The varieties of pleasure that can lead to lack of self-control, from John S. Brewer’s The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, with English Notes ().

Such lack of self control, whether “morbid” or “brutish,” may come and go, may sometimes be mastered and may other times get the upper hand. Such wickedness is super-human, not a merely human weakness, and lack of self control in such areas also goes beyond normal human bounds.

Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


In the sixth section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle looks at the particular variety of loss of self control that is prompted by anger.

The other varieties he has discussed are mostly caused either by the temptations of pleasure or by aversion to pain. Aristotle says that loss of self-control due to anger is less shameful than these, for the following reasons:

  1. Anger is at least partially obedient to the demands of our reason or better nature, but is just ineptly so. (He compares this to an over-sensitive watchdog that barks every time anyone approaches the door, whether or not it is a stranger.) Appetite (the temptation of pleasure or aversion to pain), on the other hand, seems deaf to reason. Someone conquered by anger is conquered by a flawed, primitive argument, but an argument nonetheless; someone conquered by appetite is conquered by appetite alone, not reason of any variety.
  2. Anger is more natural & normal than excessive appetites, which are abnormal and grotesque.
  3. People motivated by appetite are more prone to guile and premeditation, while anger is more of a sudden and unplanned thing.
  4. Anger is a painful condition, while the wantonness of self-indulgence is pleasurable.

Continuing where we left off in the previous section, Aristotle reminds us of the three basic varieties of bodily pleasure:

  1. human & natural (though these can be excessive)
  2. brutish (for instance, sadistic psychopathology)
  3. morbid (for instance, phobias or obsessive fetishes)

Continence, lack of self control, temperance, and intemperance only concern items in the first of these categories (although the terms can be used metaphorically to describe people and behavior in the other two).

Brutishness is less evil than vice, but is “more alarming… for [in brutish people] it is not the better part that has been perverted… they have no better part.” Still, says Aristotle, a vicious person will do ten thousand times the harm of a brutish one.

Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


In the seventh section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle compares self control with endurance.

People with self control are able to resist the temptation of pleasure when it is excessive or might lead them to do something they know is wrong. People with endurance are able to put up with pain and unpleasantness when they can and they know that such is the right thing to do. Perhaps these are just flip sides of the same basic trait.

As has been mentioned before, loss of self control means giving into temptation or retreating from what is unpleasant despite knowing that it is the wrong thing to do; intemperance means giving into temptation or shirking unpleasantness because you don’t see anything wrong with doing so. Because of this, Aristotle says the intemperate person is “without regrets, and therefore incurable [incorrigible], since a man without regrets cannot be cured.”

There is an additional issue: with regards to certain pleasures, some people are motivated by the pleasure itself, and others are motivated by quenching the pain that comes from the desire for the pleasure. Think of the gourmand as opposed to the person who is famished, or the person who loves sex and the person who is sex-starved. Each one can behave similarly in their pursuit of the pleasure they’re after, but the motives are subtly different.

With these things in mind, we can rank these various responses to pain and pleasure. Worst is the person who does wrong in pursuit of pleasures that aren’t particularly strong, just because he or she doesn’t have any compunction: the intemperate person. Not so bad are those who are tempted by strong desires, or dissuaded by great pains. Also not so bad are those who lose it due to sudden anger. Better yet is the patient or enduring person, who is able to put up with pain and unpleasantness for worthy goals. And best of all is the continent person, who habitually avoids excesses of pleasure from a well-formed character.

Next, Aristotle describes the nebbish, wimp, or pansy. The sort of person “who drags his robe after him, that he may not be annoyed with the pain of carrying it… who, imitating an invalid, does not think himself a wretched creature, although he resembles one who is.” This person is the counterpart of the intemperate person who foolishly gets carried away by even insignificant pleasures: the nebbish is stymied by even insignificant pains and inconveniences. Some such people are just naturally fragile and they can’t really be blamed for it, but in other people this tendency is blameworthy.

Aristotle says that people who are overly-fond of sport and amusement may be exhibiting a form of this: using these distractions to escape from their day-to-day troubles.

Finally, Aristotle subdivides lack of self control into two varieties:

weakness
failure, due to being carried away by emotion, to stand by the conclusions of one’s deliberation
impetuosity, precipitancy
failure to deliberate, instead allowing oneself to be led by one’s emotions
Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


In the eighth section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle reiterates that self-indulgence or intemperance is a worse vice than the weakness of incontinence or lack of self control (which is not, strictly, a vice since it is not a matter of choice but is action contrary to choice).

He seems to have been reiterating this quite a bit, and I think any good reader will have gotten the point by now. J. Cook Wilson devoted a book, The Structure of the Seventh Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, Chapters Ⅰ–Ⅹ, to the theory that this book in particular shows evidence of having been cobbled together from multiple, parallel, original fragment sources. Wilson suggests that

The compilers looked on the reputed works of Aristotle as “sacred books,” and considered themselves under obligation not to suppress any of the material which they found.

Consequently they incorporated in the text several versions of the same thing, even where they differed but slightly from one another: just as a Christian might regard the various accounts of the same events in the Gospels as of equal value and entitled to preservation in their original form.

The different ways in which they arranged and combined the duplicates may be accounted for by supposing that they endeavoured not to restore accurately an original order, but rather to make a context which would read with some appearance of continuity out of the actual fragments, adding and taking away as little as possible. There seem to be undoubted traces of connecting sentences written by a compiler: but the condition of the text indicates that it was a rule in some books at least to make such work a minimum; if this is so it would be caused by the same feeling as that which prompted the preservation of the duplicates.

So to some extent The Nicomachean Ethics reads as though someone were trying to write a transcript of Aristotle’s lectures by compiling the bits of his students’ lecture notes found in the dumpster behind the school at the end of various terms and trying to make them coherent.

This section, in particular, seems redundant — merely restating with new language and different examples what has been said before in other sections. It would be interesting to follow Wilson’s lead and to try to assemble a version of this book, or of The Nicomachean Ethics as a whole, that organizes the essentials well and perhaps less reverently, a bit like Stock did for books one through five.

Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


In the ninth section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle continues his investigation into self-control.

Self-control bears some relation to sticktoitiveness. You make up your mind and then you follow through on the decision you’ve made, even if it’s uncomfortable to do so or tempting to do something else instead. But this resembles stubbornness: sticking to your decision just because you’ve made it, even if circumstances change or it turns out to have been a bad decision.

So does self-control mean sticking to your guns when you’ve made a decision, or sticking to your guns when you’ve made a good decision, and only so long as it remains a good one?

The opening paragraph of this section is difficult to parse, and remains so in those of the translations I consulted. If I had to guess, I’d say that Aristotle is saying that a person with good self-control exercises this self-control wisely, to stick with good choices, arrived at through deliberation. He or she makes choices for the purpose of what is good, and it is really what is good that he or she is sticking to, not the choice itself (though usually these will coincide, and so it will appear that it is the choice that is the criteria).

Someone who is truly obstinate is not really exercising self-control — is not holding steadfastly to a rational choice aimed at good — but is yielding to passion and appetite in a parody of self-control. The stubbornly opinionated, for instance, yield to the pleasure of believing themselves righteously correct and hate the pain of admitting that they are wrong, and so they are hesitant to listen to good arguments in opposition to their opinions.

Aristotle mentions also that sometimes you may find that you have to break a promise (and thus behave “incontinently”) for honorable ends. (Here, he mentions the character of Neoptolemus in Sophocles’s Philoctetes, who feels honor-bound both to lie to Philoctetes for the sake of Odysseus, and not to lie for the sake of being an honest person.) This is, Aristotle says, a case of being incontinent because of being tempted by pleasure, but in this case the pleasure is the pleasure of being honorable, not some “disgraceful pleasure,” so this does not count as self-indulgent or incontinent.

Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


In the tenth section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle wraps up his investigation into self-control.

He hearkens back to a couple of earlier arguments: the twelfth and thirteenth sections of book six in which he distinguished practical wisdom from mere cleverness (practical wisdom aims at what is good, while cleverness may aim at any old thing), and the second section of this book in which he insisted that incontinence is not a variety of practical wisdom (in other words, the incontinent person doesn’t change his or her mind at the last minute because of a sudden better grasp of the situation).

He brings forward a new analogy to explain the difference between the incontinent person and the intemperate one. The incontinent person is like a city that has good laws on the books but that doesn’t enforce them; the intemperate person is like a city with bad laws.

He also emphasizes here that continence is not a binary thing that you either have or don’t have. It’s measured on a scale — the continent person has more self-control than the average person, the incontinent person less.

Finally, he notes that incontinence due to impetuosity (failure to deliberate at all) is easier to correct than incontinence due to weakness (inability to stick to the choices you make by deliberation). Also, incontinence that is acquired by bad habit is easier to correct than incontinence that is innate (though he notes that habitual incontinence can become as-if-innate over time).

Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


We’re not quite finished with book seven of The Nicomachean Ethics yet, but Aristotle shifts topics here, and I thought I’d try to do a wrap-up of his ten — sometimes overlapping, and at least once just plain contradictory — sections on the subject of self-control.

Self-control is what you exhibit when, after you have deliberated on the right course of action and have chosen the right thing to do, temptation tries to steer you in another direction and you resist temptation, doing the right thing anyway. Lack of self-control happens when you are unable to resist this temptation, and you choose wisely but don’t follow through on the choice you have made.

This differs from temperance and intemperance, in that the temperate person doesn’t really suffer from strong temptations to begin with, and the intemperate person doesn’t choose wisely to begin with. Temperance and intemperance are a virtue and a vice, because they are character traits formed from habitual choice. Self-control and its absence aren’t a virtue and vice but are some other sort of thing (lack of self control isn’t a choice but acting regardless of choice).

So self-control is not the same as temperance, nor is it quite the same as saintliness (a nearly-divine, superhuman self-control). Similarly, lack of self-control is not the same as intemperance, nor is it quite the same as brutishness (a nearly-subhuman savagery).

Self-control is also distinct from stubbornness. The person with self-control decides to do the right thing and sticks with that determination. The stubborn person, by contrast, makes a decision and sticks with the decision, whether or not it is, or ends up being, the right thing. Stubbornness indeed is a variety of intemperance: favoring the pleasure of self-righteousness or decisiveness over actually being virtuous.

Self-control comes in degrees; it’s not an either you have it or you don’t sort of thing. Some people are more continent, some people less so.

Self-control in the face of tempting pleasure is something like endurance in the face of discouraging pain. Some people are tempted by pleasure; some by quenching the pain of desire for pleasure. (In the one case, we would need self-control; in the other, we would need endurance.)

The nebbish lacks endurance, and folds under insignificant inconveniences; people who are overly-fond of recreation may also escape the unpleasantnesses of life in this way.

Lack of self-control is not the same as indecisiveness. It can be difficult to weigh competing ethical demands, and circumstances can change, so it is possible to make a deliberate ethical choice and still have good reason to change your mind at some point. Changing your mind in the service of virtue is no vice.

That said, lack of self-control is not some sort of last-minute prudence, as some would have it, in which a virtuous action looks unappealing up close and so you rationally abandon it. Lack of self-control is never a variety of practical wisdom.

Lack of self-control can be seen as a lapse of knowledge, akin to being asleep, insane, or intoxicated. Although incontinent people can articulate the reasoning behind the choice they made (but then abandoned) this only means that they know how to fake reasonable understanding; they haven’t really understood. Somehow they have lost track of the particular premise in a syllogism in which they have accepted the universal. You are more likely to do this when there is a competing syllogism whose conclusion offers the bait of sensual pleasure.

Lack of self-control can be divided into four varieties and two types:

It can be general (lack of self-control in the face of necessary pleasures, like food or sex — the same general subject matter as temperance), in which case it is lack of self-control proper. Or it can be specific (lack of self-control in the face of certain pleasures that, while good in themselves, can be carried to extremes, like victory, honor, or wealth), in which case it isn’t really lack of self-control, but is sometimes called that metaphorically.

A third variety is lack of self-control in the face of certain things that aren’t typically pleasant, but are so in certain people due to some pathology or other: people who obsessively eat paper, or people who have a sadistic psychopathology, for instance. People who have a lack of self-control as the result of pathology aren’t really exhibiting lack of self-control as Aristotle is using the term; neither brutal savages, who are something “beyond the limits of vice” — more alarming perhaps, but probably less harmful than actual vice.

A fourth variety is not prompted by the temptation of pleasure but by the fury of anger. This is less-blameworthy than the varieties prompted by pleasure, as anger is a natural human thing (whereas excessive pursuit of pleasure is abnormal and grotesque), is partially obedient to reason, is less-premeditated, and is inherently unenjoyable.

The two types of lack of self-control are 1) failure to stick with the conclusions of your deliberation due to being carried away by emotion (“weakness”), and 2) failure to deliberate in the first place, letting emotion take over from reason (“impetuosity”).

Of these:

  • Impetuosity is easier to correct than weakness.
  • Lack of self-control acquired through bad habit is easier to correct than innate lack of self-control.
  • Between the intemperate person and the person with a lack of self-control, Aristotle is of two minds as to which is more correctable. On the one hand, you can persuade the intemperate person using reason, while the person without self-control is evidently impervious to reason. But, on the other hand, the person without self-control performs wrong actions regretfully, while the intemperate person is without regrets and therefore without any motive to change.
Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


The concluding sections of book seven of The Nicomachean Ethics concern pleasure, and whether it is something good, bad, or it-depends. Pleasure is also the subject of book ten.

These sections also appear in The Eudemean Ethics, which seems to be considered a less-mature treatment of the subject by Aristotle. For this reason, some of our panel of translators and commentators omit them in favor of book ten (Browne, Gillies, Lewes, Vincent), include them as an appendix (Chase), or include them but label them “superfluous” (Grant); others are content to include them on equal footing with the rest of The Nicomachean Ethics.

I think what I’ll do is go through these sections through to the end of book seven, then skip ahead to book ten before circling back and finishing off with books eight and nine (both of which concern friendship).

But first, a quick review of what Aristotle has already said about pleasure and pain:

Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


In the eleventh section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle looks at three arguments that “some people” make in opposition to the idea that pleasure is a, or the, Good. (Many of our panel of translators and commentators say that Aristotle is largely replying to the theories of Speusippus.)

  1. Good and Pleasure are different sorts of things, so no pleasure can be a good. This because:
    1. Every pleasure is a sort of activity; but a good is a static end, not an activity.
    2. Temperate people avoid pleasures; but virtuous people (temperance is a virtue) don’t shun what is good.
    3. Practical wisdom teaches us how to avoid pain, but not how to pursue pleasure.
    4. Pleasures interfere with rational thinking; for example, it’s difficult to keep your syllogisms straight in the midst of a good rogering.
    5. Every good is a product of some art, but there is no such thing as an “art” of pleasure.
    6. Children and brutes pursue pleasure, so it isn’t the sort of ultimate end only refined people know to pursue.
  2. Some pleasures may also be goods, but most are not. This because:
    1. There are some pleasures that are “actually base and objects of reproach.”
    2. There are harmful, unhealthy pleasures.
  3. Although all pleasures are good, at least in so far as they are pleasant, the ultimate good cannot be pleasure. This because:
    1. As argument #1a also puts it, pleasure is a process and the ultimate good is an end.

Aristotle has already declared eudaimonia — happiness, fulfillment, flourishing — to be the ultimate end of human life, and he says that most people would consider pleasure to be at least a component of happiness (and wouldn’t you expect eudaimonia itself to be pleasant?). So he wants to investigate these arguments critically, which he will do in the following sections.

Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


In the twelfth section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle begins to answer the arguments against pleasure as a/the good that he noted in the previous section.

Some of his counter-arguments address multiple arguments at once, and so it can be hard to keep track of which is which, but I’ll try to bring them under some sort of ordering scheme here and in the sections that follow.

Arguments:

1a
Good and Pleasure are different sorts of things, so no pleasure can be a good. This is because every pleasure is a sort of activity; but a good is a static end, not an activity.
3a
Although all pleasures are good, at least in so far as they are pleasant, the ultimate good cannot be pleasure. This is because, as argument #1a also puts it, pleasure is a process and the ultimate good is an end.

Aristotle’s answer:

  • Remember that there are two types of goods: things that are good in and of themselves, and things that are good for something. This is also true of things, states of being, processes, and the like: some are good, or bad, in general; others only good or bad with respect to some particular person or circumstance.
  • While it’s true that the pleasures of, say, quenching hunger or thirst can be thought of as incidental pleasures accompanying our transition to an end-state of satisfaction, you can also think of these pleasures as accompanying the unimpeded activity of our activities of drinking and eating: in other words, the pleasure is in the activity itself, not in the end-state it’s aiming for. Note that there are other pleasures of unimpeded activity (the pleasure of contemplation, for instance) that don’t involve returning our bodies to a satisfied end-state but that are pleasurable all the same. Note also that there are different sorts of pleasures involved in eating whatever is put before you because you are famished, and eating a delicious meal with just an ordinary appetite; gustatory pleasure isn’t just the pleasure of banishing hunger.
  • Not all pleasures are means towards ends. Some indeed are themselves ends. They don’t just arise from attaining some end, but they arise from the process of engaging in activity. Sometimes it’s the journey, not the destination.

Argument:

1d
Good and Pleasure are different sorts of things, so no pleasure can be a good. This is because pleasures interfere with rational thinking; for example, it’s difficult to keep your syllogisms straight in the midst of a good rogering.

Aristotle’s answer:

  • While there are pleasures that can impede rational thought, there are also pleasures that accompany rational thought and don’t impede it at all.

Argument:

2b
Some pleasures may also be goods, but most are not. This is because there are harmful, unhealthy pleasures.

Aristotle’s answer:

  • It’s a case of bad logic to say that because some pleasant things are unhealthy, pleasures must not be good. It would be like saying that because some healthy things are expensive, healthy things must not be good. There’s just no connection. If a pleasure is unhealthy it is bad at promoting health, but is not simply bad for that reason.

Argument:

1e
Good and Pleasure are different sorts of things, so no pleasure can be a good. This is because every good is a product of some art, but there is no such thing as an “art” of pleasure.

Aristotle’s answer:

  • Arts concern the creation of things; pleasure is a variety of activity. So there is no such thing as an art of an activity, though there can be an art of exercising a certain faculty that gives rise to an activity in pursuit of a concrete end. So, okay, if you grant that every good is the product of an art, perhaps pleasure cannot be such a good.
  • But in some sense, the arts of the perfumer or the gourmet are arts of pleasure, are they not?

Arguments:

1b
Good and Pleasure are different sorts of things, so no pleasure can be a good. This is because temperate people avoid pleasures; but virtuous people (temperance is a virtue) don’t shun what is good.
1c
…and because practical wisdom teaches us how to avoid pain, but not how to pursue pleasure.
1f
…and because children and brutes pursue pleasure, so it isn’t the sort of ultimate end only refined people know to pursue.

Aristotle’s answer:

  • Again, there are some pleasures that are good without qualification, and other pleasures can be good or bad for different people and in different circumstances. Children and brutes pursue the latter sort without the benefit of practical wisdom; the temperate person knows to avoid those pleasures that can lead to lack of self-control and other types of excess, but even the temperate person has pleasures.
Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


In the thirteenth section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle continues to answer the arguments against pleasure as a/the good that he noted in section eleven.

First, he notes that pain certainly is bad. Some pain is just plain bad without qualification; other pain is bad because it interferes in our pursuits. This doesn’t meet any of the original objections head-on. It seems to me to suffer from some of the same problems as the blanket objections to pleasure that Aristotle is arguing against. Even if pain is typically a bad to be avoided, isn’t it sometimes something to be sought out? The pain of hunger is to be avoided… unless you’re trying to lose weight and then it’s a sign that your body is burning fat. The pain of nausea is to be avoided… unless you’ve been poisoned, in which case, reach for the ipecac.

Aristotle’s point is that if pain is clearly bad, its opposite, pleasure, must be good.

Aristotle is responding to the views of Speusippus, which must have been very tempting to him, since they have a very Aristotelian find-the-happy-medium feel to them. To Speusippus, both pain and pleasure were deviations from the good in opposite directions. So to him, pleasure wasn’t the opposite of pain, but pleasure and pain were equally opposite to the happy medium — the same way Aristotle’s opposing vices (e.g. cowardice and rashness) were opposites to the virtue (courage).

Aristotle next responds to some of the specific arguments he outlined earlier:

Argument:

2a
Some pleasures may also be goods, but most are not. This is because there are some pleasures that are “actually base and objects of reproach.”

Aristotle’s answer:

  • “[I]f certain pleasures are bad, that does not prevent the chief good from being some pleasure, just as the chief good may be some form of knowledge though certain kinds of knowledge are bad. Perhaps it is even necessary, if each disposition has unimpeded activities, that, whether the activity (if unimpeded) of all our dispositions or that of some one of them is happiness, this should be the thing most worthy of our choice; and this activity is pleasure. Thus the chief good would be some pleasure, though most pleasures might perhaps be bad without qualification.”
  • You must consider pleasure to at least be part of a happy life; a person who is virtuous in every other way but is experiencing great pain, not pleasure, can’t be said to be happy.

Argument:

1f
Good and Pleasure are different sorts of things, so no pleasure can be a good. This is because children and brutes pursue pleasure, so it isn’t the sort of ultimate end only refined people know to pursue.

Aristotle’s answer:

  • This is actually a point in favor of the idea that pleasure is the chief good. If everybody, even brutes and children, pursues pleasure, there must be something to it.
  • People who pursue base pleasures don’t necessarily have the wrong idea about what is good, but are kind of like moths who fly into lanterns by mistake, guided by a generally-correct instinct to aim for light.

In this section, Aristotle comes very close to endorsing hedonism: the idea that pleasure is the ultimate end of activity. This is not the conclusion he comes to in book ten, however.

Some of our panel of translators and commentators, particularly Muirhead and Stewart, have tried to reconcile the two points of view.

They suggest that “pleasure” has two subtly different meanings in the books seven and ten. In this book, book seven, Aristotle defines pleasure as a thing, as the unbridled exercise of a faculty, which is itself a good thing. In book ten, Aristotle defines pleasure more as an epiphenomenon that crowns or accompanies the unbridled exercise of a faculty, where it is the activity itself, and not the pleasure that accompanies it, that is the good.

So in book seven, Aristotle says that pleasure is the unbridled exercise of a faculty; the unbridled exercise of a faculty is good; therefore, pleasure is good. In book ten, Aristotle says that the unbridled exercise of a faculty is pleasant; the unbridled exercise of a faculty is the good; therefore the good is pleasant. A different perspective, but not exactly contradictory.

I was reminded, while reading this, of Robert Nozick’s Experience Machine. In this thought experiment, Nozick asks you to imagine that you can plug yourself into a machine that thoroughly simulates reality for you in such a convincing way that you cannot help but believe that it is reality. Furthermore, you can program this simulation to maximize your pleasure beyond anything possible in real life. Would you plug in?

Nozick noted that there’s something repulsive about the thought of plugging in to this machine, and concluded that this repulsiveness means we must want not only to feel pleasure, but to feel it as part of our real participation in the real world. He decided that therefore hedonism must not be correct — that the ultimate good must be more than just pleasure.

Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics


In the final section of the seventh book of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle continues to answer the arguments against pleasure as a/the good that he noted in section eleven, and then he tries to imagine the perfect, divine pleasure.

Arguments:

2
Some pleasures may also be goods, but most are not. This is because there are some pleasures that are “actually base and objects of reproach,” and because there are harmful, unhealthy pleasures.

Aristotle’s answer:

Aristotle reminds us of his division of pleasures into the necessary, bodily pleasures, like the pleasures from satisfying appetites for food or sex, and certain other pleasures like those from gaining wealth, earning honors, and the like. Some people say that the bodily pleasures are base and to be avoided, while only certain of the other pleasures are worth pursuing. But Aristotle wonders if this is the case, why the pains associated with the body are still considered bads to be avoided. If the good associated with relieving pain isn’t really a good to be pursued, doesn’t this mean that pain isn’t really a bad to be avoided? That is absurd; everybody avoids bodily pain and tries to relieve it when it happens.

Aristotle says that when we say an intemperate person is bad for pursuing bodily pleasures, we don’t really mean that the pleasures themselves aren’t good, but that the person pursuing them is doing so excessively or in the wrong way.

There are two reasons why bodily pleasures are particularly attractive. One is that they dispel bodily pain. The contrast with the opposing pain can make bodily pleasures appear to be more pleasant than they actually are. The other is because of a more complex issue of human psychology.

Bodily pleasures have a vivid, tangible intensity. People who are unaccustomed to more refined pleasures are easily overwhelmed by such intense bodily pleasures. In fact, some people artificially induce pains in themselves just in order to heighten the pleasure of relieving them. (I’ve noticed this in myself. My coffee addiction is largely motivated by being able to wake up in the morning and know immediately a very pleasant thing I can do for myself — that is, to make myself a cup of joe — that is mostly pleasant because it dispels the withdrawal symptoms of waking up after many caffeineless hours.)

Although there is a school of thought that says that all creatures strive for a satisfied equilibrium point — hungers satisfied but not over-sated, neither too hot nor too warm, and so forth — for many people, such a neutral state is actually painful. All animal life, humans included, is a sort of writhing, violent struggle. Why are children so prone to ecstatic extremes of emotion? It is because of their physical growth — this writhing struggle at its most violent — causing “a kind of chronic intoxication.” People tend to pursue bodily pleasures and to banish bodily pains in such a way as to throw themselves off-kilter, increasing the violence of their mood swings and encouraging yet more destabilizing pursuits.

Wiser people pursue healthy pleasures — ones that aren’t simply a remedy to a contrasting bodily pain but ones that enhance or improve or participate in an already healthy faculty. Such pleasures are ones that you cannot pursue to a destabilizing excess.

Why is it, Aristotle asks, that we can’t simply discover our pleasant thing, and then stick with it, milking the pleasure all our lives long? This is because we are imperfect, material creatures: part soul and part body. By honoring the pleasures of one part of us, we may neglect or even harm the other part. If we were of a more unified stuff, rather than this hastily-swirled alloy, there would be a pleasure that was also the pleasure — the best one and the only one we would have need to pursue. God, for instance, must have such a single, continuous, and simple pleasure — not a pleasure of repair or restoration, but one of a state of rest that is already perfect. Our pleasures, though, are not of this kind. Many involve change and transition. It is what is bad and defective in us that loves change so much; the best pleasures are simple and unchanging.

This last paragraph introduces many new and strange ideas about human and divine nature. It seems an odd note for Aristotle to end the book on, though Grant says that he will bring some of this up again in book ten.

Index to the Nicomachean Ethics series

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics