Why it is your duty to stop supporting the government →
ethics →
practice makes perfect; virtue ethics
and I started to ramble on a bit about how I first came to be scared of Nazis and why they still have me looking over my shoulder today.
is part three of Nazis Creep Me Out, subtitled: The Road to Auschwitz is Paved with Good Telemarketers
Maybe it’s a little phobic to worry so much about the possibility of your neighbors turning into cogs in a mass killing machine.
Maybe not.
One estimate was that (), governments had organized people in such a way as to murder about 170,000,000 noncombatants off of the field of war (typically their own citizens) in .
An additional number of people, about a quarter as large a total, were killed in the course of warfare in .
Some back-of-the-envelope calculations show that that comes to about two and a half million each year, about 6,500 per day, about one every 13 seconds.
Even as a public health problem, that’s big:
Compare it to, say, malaria, which kills over a million people each year, or tuberculosis and AIDS, which kill some two million each, for instance.
But there’s something worse about a calamity that’s deliberately inflicted — worse and at the same time something that requires attention:
it seems to be not only something that people might hope to prevent, but something that people might be convinced not to commit.
That at least gives us another angle than we’ve got, say, on tuberculosis.
There’s a huge preexisting canon of poetic “why?”s about “man’s inhumanity to man” that I didn’t really intend to try to add any more redundancies to, so I’ll stop there.
Just about everybody has thought about this problem at some point or other, maybe even dwelled on it.
And then most of us just kind of give up.
The giving up is accompanied by a resigned commemoration that goes a little something like this:
The human race — so full of noble aspirations, so capable of warm emotions, uniquely gifted in our capacity for communication and altruism — and yet ironically so brutal, so unrepentantly savage, so war-loving.
We’ve always been this way, and we always will be, in the absence of some science-fiction solution, until (chances are) we finally wipe ourselves out.
The cost of this is so high, and has been for so long, that this desperation I feel to find a solution is surely not new, and if our good intentions and our cleverness and reason were enough to solve the problem, surely we would at least have a solution in sight by now… but we don’t.
We can continue to chant “peace” until we’re blue in the face, but it isn’t going to change this fact.
Wars, massacres — nobody wants them to happen, but they will, and it’s a fool’s errand to try to bring us a world without them.
This outlook may be as true as it is pessimistic.
But it really misses the point that it pretends to be addressing so soberly, and becomes an unhealthy evasion.
I see two related catches:
First, it poses the problem of these two and a half million deaths per year as a problem demanding an all-or-nothing solution.
Second, and because of this, it can only imagine a utopian, top-down solution.
The first catch comes from looking at the pile of mangled bodies from a century, or from a war, or from a policy and, being overwhelmed, wanting to come up with something that would prevent them all at once.
For example: What if we had a world-wide government, democratic of course, that guaranteed political freedoms, and had a universally respected judiciary that peoples and countries could turn to to resolve grievances?
Then we wouldn’t need wars and massacres to solve our problems!
And pigs could perch on phone lines instead of taking up valuable real estate!
(Some darker utopian visions stem from a similar urge:
What if instead of our tribe and their tribe always going to war over this and that, there were only our tribe and theirs had become extinct?)
If in looking for a solution you find none that promise to more-or-less completely solve the problem except for grandiose sci-fi utopian schemes you have no hope of implementing — the next step isn’t to give up, but to back up.
The point is that a proposal that lessens the problem, or a small first step that doesn’t do much in itself but is the first step in slowly, incrementally or gradually solving the problem, may be a good proposal.
Even something that merely prevents things from getting worse is worth listening to when the stakes are so high!
Humanity may not ever find an on/off switch for this horror, but perhaps it can learn to turn the volume down.
The second catch is in assuming that because the solution is necessarily so gigantic and universal in its nature that it must be something that is implemented top-down — from the headquarters of the United Nations, or via Pax Americana, or from a spacecraft sent by benevolent aliens, or from God.
I think there may be a solution that’s admittedly gradual and slow, but also promises to be practical and to show returns more than proportional to the extent that it is applied.
Furthermore, it’s not top-down — it isn’t even bottom-up — it’s anybody-out.
It necessarily, crucially, begins with and within individual people.
(And no, it’s not tax resistance, but for me that’s part of how it’s blooming).
It comes down to this:
I don’t think there are enough sufficiently angry people in the world, or enough cruel psychopaths in the world, to murder two and a half million people a year all by themselves.
They need help and they need accomplices — people who aren’t themselves inclined to do these things but are willing to do them anyway by convincing themselves they’re doing something else, be it “following orders” or “doing my duty” or “earning a living somehow.”
As Hannah Arendt demonstrated in her examples, where enough of these people can be found, the wheels of what she calls “administrative massacre” are greased.
But she also found that where enough counterexamples are found, they become monkeywrenches in this same machinery.
And where they’re especially numerous, they can break the machinery entirely.
Every “administrative massacre” will be a little different — the victims will be chosen differently, and different methods will be used.
What will the gas chambers look like next time — a mushroom cloud, a virus released on a subway, a gulag archipelago for terrorist suspects?
Who is stacking the bricks?
Who is conducting the trains?
You’ll know them by their excuses — “what can you do?”
“I’ve got nothing against them personally”
“it’s my job”
“somebody else would do it if I didn’t”
“I’ve got a family to feed”
“I don’t make the rules”
“they don’t pay me to think about that.”
And you can hear these excuses around you today, right where you live.
People who are doing rude, anti-social, dishonest things but who insist that they aren’t rude, or anti-social, or dishonest people — it’s their job, or it’s the rules, or it’s just a part they’re playing.
I try very hard never to make these kind of excuses.
Which is to say that I try not to put myself into the sorts of positions where excuses like these might seem reasonable to me.
I think I may avoid killing a Jew some day this way.
And when telemarketers call I tell them, politely but firmly, that it is rude to call up a stranger just to try to sell them something, and won’t they please consider another line of work.
“What can you do?”
“it’s my job”
“somebody else would do it if I didn’t”
“I’ve got a family to feed”
“I don’t make the rules”
“they don’t pay me to think about that.”
I’m as persistent as they are, and eventually they hang up.
Still, I think I may save a Jew some day this way.
I make up aphorisms for myself, sometimes paraphrasing from others when my creativity isn’t up to it.
Here’s one: “Have the courage to fight for what you believe in, the stubbornness not to fight without believing, and the wisdom to know the difference.”
Usually, like this one, they aren’t very good, either not very catchy or too glib, but it keeps me thinking about it.
And steps like this are my solution, anyone-out. We’re anyone. Over and out.
Janet Jackson and Justin Timberlake performing at the Super Bowl halftime show
Watching the Super Bowl and hearing all of the impassioned debating about the wisdom of two-point-conversion attempts and whether or not the punt is overused reminded me of a parable my mythical friend Ishmael Gradsdovic likes to tell.
After high school, Ishmael and three of his friends went to the local community college for a spell.
Those three friends, having been enraptured by the World Series (the “Bay Bridge” or “Earthquake” series in which the Oakland Athletics hung the San Francisco Giants out to dry), decided that they wanted to be on the college’s baseball squad the following season.
(Ishmael himself, never one for the mainstream, was more into fencing than baseball.)
Now none of these friends had played any organized ball since little league, so they had a little catching up to do if they wanted to make the team.
In the best “three little pigs” fashion, each had a different approach.
Mannie figured the best way to learn would be to consult the experts.
He found books about baseball written by some of the wisest and most experienced practitioners of the sport.
Walter Alston, Branch Rickey, Earl Weaver, Leo Durocher, Whitey Herzog, Casey Stengel — he absorbed their maxims as though they were the words of the Buddha addressing his assembled monks.
(And often the advice made for difficult meditation indeed, for instance Stengel’s observation that “good pitching will always stop good hitting and vice-versa.”)
Jerry, on the other hand, suspected that there were flaws in the established wisdom and that even the experts were probably relying on folklore and hunches that wouldn’t stand up under scientific scrutiny.
So he looked into statistics.
Baseball is probably the most obsessively statistically-analyzed game in the history of the world, so Jerry quickly found himself buried in statistical abstracts and databases.
He spent his free time running computer simulations of various batting lineup orders and strategic choices.
He came to believe some heterodox but statistically defensible conclusions, for instance that it’s a poor idea to put your worst batter in the #9 position, that the sacrifice fly is overused, and that base stealing should be attempted less often.
Ari didn’t much go in for this theory stuff.
He was more interested in playing ball.
So once he learned the rules of the game at the college level and how they differed from what he’d learned of the game in little league, he put the reading materials away.
Any chance he got, he’d join in pick-up games and softball leagues and even hitting fly balls for kids to shag.
Jerry and Mannie didn’t agree on everything, but they did think Ari was foolish not to spend more time brushing up on the finer points of the game.
“You’re going to miscalibrate your instincts playing all this sand lot stuff,” Mannie told him.
“The game is played much more intensely in competitive college ball than at some weekend keg game.”
Jerry agreed: “You’re only going to learn the most rudimentary skills playing this way.
Then what will happen when you’re in a real game and some situation comes along that you’ve never encountered or even thought about before?
Anyone can learn the 90% of playing baseball, but it’s that last subtle 10% that distinguishes the all-stars from the also-rans.”
But still they’d come to his games, and even throw on the gloves from time to time and participate.
But mostly they liked to argue. Mannie would cite precedent and Jerry would throw back percentages to the third decimal place.
Ari would listen, ask questions, occasionally “p’shaw,” and sometimes try out their ideas on the field.
Well, to make a long story less long, it eventually came time for tryouts.
The coach was impressed with Mannie’s knowledge of baseball history and strategy and with Jerry’s complex understanding of the interplay of the many variables that make up a game.
In their first mock-up game, he had Mannie start in left field, Jerry in center field, and Ari in right.
But Mannie didn’t play as well as he’d hoped.
He started the game with the confidence that comes from having the hall of fame sitting on your shoulders and whispering into your ear.
But although he knew just how to set down a bunt, somehow he couldn’t get the bat and ball to cooperate.
And though he knew exactly how to shift in left field to compensate for the strengths of opposing batters and the number of outs and men on base, he wasn’t so good at judging how to field a ball coming at him on a trick bounce.
He was playing right, but not playing too well.
And Jerry found that his statistics weren’t all that helpful on the field.
He could tell you with great accuracy and precision what it is that he ought to do in any situation either at the plate or in the field, but when he threw the ball to the correct base, the accuracy and precision of the throw was wanting.
Ari had struggles of his own.
His fielding and throwing was better, his batting more successful, but his friends were right that this game was different from what he’d been playing before.
He usually found that his instincts scaled pretty well from what he’d learned in the weekend leagues to how he needed to play now.
But one of his rifle-shot throws from right field, accurate as it was, came in too late to catch a runner who’d taken a good lead, and he realized that Mannie and Jerry would have correctly told him to hit the cut-off man.
But when the team’s final roster was announced, Ari was on it and Mannie and Jerry weren’t.
The coach explained that while Mannie and Jerry knew how the game oughta be played, Ari knew how to play.
“You’ve still got plenty to learn, but it’s gonna be refinements to the mechanism.
Those other guys, we’d have to start from the ground up.”
Well, what does this have to do with the weather on Mars?
It’s meant to be a sunday school style promotion of virtue ethics (which I mentioned ) and also a way for me to excuse myself in rambling on a bit more about my theory that the way to build your own ethical fortifications is to start one brick at a time rather than trying to design instant castles on paper.
The best way to become virtuous is to practice virtue — informed perhaps by ethical theories but never expecting that you will be able to apply these theories algorithmically as a substitute for conscientious (and fuzzy) judgment.
Being virtuous in ordinary, day-to-day situations is a way to prepare for being virtuous when confronted with difficult, unanticipated and critical situations.
If you get in the habit of making good, worthy choices this will strengthen your will in difficult times like no theory can.
How do you know which choices are good and worthy of the virtuous life?
Well, I think it can help to be informed by ethical philosophy, and I think there’s probably plenty to be absorbed from folklore, literature, religion, and the like.
But these aren’t to be used purely intellectually, or taken on faith, but should be understood as things that have informed and nurtured a larger ethical “sixth sense” — one that almost certainly needs continuing nurturing.
One way this ethical sense reveals itself is through the sensation of guilt.
Sometimes guilt is just part of the processing of mistakes and unintended consequences, and should be attended to just because the way you learn is through making mistakes, noticing them and trying not to repeat them.
Guilt also is often evidence of a disconnect between the morals you have or think you should have and those that actually guide your actions.
Such cases are opportunities to examine this disconnect.
If your actual motives do not match some moral theory you’d like to think you hold, one or the other needs to change.
Choose carefully, and then silently, wordlessly, but honestly retell the story of who you are and what you believe.
Which is to say that the intellectualized, verbalized, symbolic summary of your ethical beliefs is never going to quite capture them in their full natures.
But also that these ethics need to be a balanced combination of prescriptive moral guidance and descriptive psychological insight.
If you respond to the question “what are my ethical values” with a prescriptive moral code — that’s evidence that you aren’t paying close enough attention to what your ethical values really are but instead are expressing a wish about what those ethical values should be or a declaration of what you’d like other people to think those values are.
The trick is to continually adjust your conscious understanding of your ethics in the light of observation, understanding and experience until you no longer feel guilt — not because you have learned to ignore it, deny it or suppress it (on the contrary, you treasure it as valuable feedback) — but because this disconnect has vanished:
the ethical standard you hold yourself to has become more human and more attuned to the real world, and at the same time you have become the sort of person that you can be proud of, and so you and your ethics have met across the chasm of this disconnect, and the source of much of your guilt has dried up.
In reality this goal may never fully be met.
Chances are the best we can hope for is to be on an asymptotic trajectory toward being our own hero.
Still — this isn’t such a bad fate, is it?
Sartwell wanted to explore “public virtue and moral character” by examining five of his heroes in “a kind of bootstrap operation in which the cardinal virtues of public figures emerge from the biographies, while the biographies themselves are in part constructed to display these same qualities.”
The five heroes he chose, an idiosyncratic collection, were Emma Goldman, Voltairine de Cleyre, Barry Goldwater, John Fire Lame Deer, and Malcolm X.
In looking at the lives of these five American leaders he admires, Sartwell attempts to discover what sets them apart.
He believes that “ethics is an empirical inquiry” that is best studied by observing ethical people; and certainly people learn ethics more from exemplars than from systems.
In studying his five American heroes, he reduces their primary virtues to four: commitment to something greater than their own ambitions (and the courage that goes along with being committed to something difficult or unpopular), self-reflection, integrity, and connectedness.
In addition to this is leadership, but this is partially derived from the four primary virtues and partially an artifact of how he picked his heroes.
It’s an interesting read, and an interesting project.
Sartwell spends a lot of time noting the less-admirable behavior of his heroes and making the case that their most notorious vices were often just their best virtues being played out in a context where they led to unfortunate results.
Alas, the biographies are so brief, and the attention Sartwell gives to this less-pretty side of things is so unsparing, that his heroes wind up looking less heroic than they perhaps ought.
I would have been happier to read some more thoroughly fleshed-out examples of particularly heroic episodes in these lives.
This book may make you more interested in examining and systematizing who and how you admire.
I was musing about the state of the discipline of ethics, and noting that while there is a lot of attention given in that field to what ethics means and how to go about discovering correct, intelligible, and consistent ethical principles, there doesn’t seem to be much attention given to the problem of how one goes about becoming someone who makes ethical decisions.
How does one avoid the many temptations to do evil?
How does one recognize good and evil alternatives amidst the camouflage they often use?
How does one develop a good character so that ethical decision-making becomes second nature?
It seems to me that there ought to be some sort of discipline that covers this ground.
I imagine maybe going to an ethics dojo to get a black belt in being good.
The social scientists and psychologists have devised all sorts of interesting experiments that have revealed a variety of quirks and deficiencies in human ethical reasoning and decision-making — could we not also devise clever defenses against them and practice them to get better?
It’s as if we had a society full of biologists, epidemiologists, chemists, anatomists and the like, all of whom had developed tremendous insights into the causes of the physical maladies with which we are plagued, and yet we hadn’t gotten around to inventing the discipline of medicine or building hospitals or manufacturing medicines.
I’ve been reading through an abridged version of The Nicomachean Ethics and I note that to Aristotle:
…[T]he branch of philosophy on which we are at present engaged differs from the others in not being a subject of merely intellectual interest — I mean we are not concerned to know what goodness essentially is, but how we are to become good men, for this alone gives the study its practical value…
What happened? Where did this variety of ethics go?
What if all of our contemporary moral discourse were a kind of cargo cult in which we had picked up fragments of a long lost, once-coherent and -rational moral philosophy, and had proceeded forward with these fragments, not really knowing what we were doing, and had constructed a bunch of nonsense that didn’t work and could not work in principle?
Alasdair MacIntyre, in After Virtue (), argues that this indeed is what happened, and this explains why our moral discourse is such a mess.
Why is it that when we argue with each other about moral issues — war and
peace, liberty or equality, life or choice, family values or gay rights, what
have you — we make our case in a form that seems to be one of logical,
rational argument (“my point of view is true because…”), but the effect of
what we say seems to be only like that of imperative statements (“Join me in
supporting…”) or exclamations (“…is the bestest!”)? Why do pro-life folks and
pro-choice folks (for instance) keep arguing with each other when there is no
resolution to their argument?
MacIntyre believes that we are unconsciously reenacting forms of argument that once made sense, since people once did have a common ground of morality they could advance together from rationally, but that we have since lost this in a Tower of Babel-like catastrophe.
As a result, our moral arguments today are interminable because the values
they express are essentially incommensurable. Though the claims of the
emotivists are not
universally and necessarily true, they happen to be true for contemporary
moral philosophy: when people make moral arguments today they really
are just making imperative statements or exclamations of
(dis)approval while disguising these as rational arguments about facts.
Modern moral philosophy has adopted the idea that all moral systems must eventually descend on certain first principles that everyone must choose for themselves and for which there are no rational criteria for a correct choice: you cannot get an “ought” from an “is” as they say.
As a result, the only way you can defend any results you derive from such a moral framework to someone else who does not share that framework is in a form that ultimately reduces to “my first principles are better than your first principles, nyaah nyaah.”
This means that all of this arguing is necessarily for nought. And modern
moral philosophy has been absolutely unsuccessful in finding any way out of
this predicament.
As a result, the emotivist explanation of moral argument is the dominant and most rational one, and so people who engage in moral arguments are essentially trying to manipulate others and at the same time to resist being manipulated, knowing on some level that there is no rational resolution, which leads to the perpetual histrionic impasse and jousting with talking-points that keeps the television news networks and political parties in business.
Although a number of modern philosophers have suggested that this is a
necessary feature of moral philosophy — that there are no right answers in
ethics or that the whole field of inquiry is some sort of an illusion — MacIntyre says that this state of affairs isn’t necessarily true but
is really just the result of the catastrophe that shattered a once-coherent
ethics.
Our current concept of “the moral” was invented in the 17th–19th centuries to cover “rules of conduct which are neither theological nor legal nor aesthetic.” The philosophical project of justifying these rules developed along with it.
The classical world didn’t have this concept.
The words we appropriated for it — moralis or etikos — meant something more like our word “character.” The failure of this philosophical project of justifying our received moral rules is “the historical background against which the predicaments of our own culture can become intelligible.”
MacIntyre works backwards through Kierkegaard, Kant, Diderot, and Hume, and
says that they were unable to find a rational ground for morality in choice,
in reason, or in passion and desire. Each was capable of decisively refuting
some of these grounds, but each failed to show that their own best guess was
capable of doing the job.
These philosophers had to fail because their project — to somehow derive morality from human nature — was incoherent and doomed.
The morality that these philosophers were trying to justify consisted of
surviving remnants of morality from an earlier time. The ancestor of these
morals were the virtues that Aristotle discussed in The
Nicomachean Ethics, in which ethics is considered to be the science of
how we govern our lives so as to best meet the ends of human living: the human
telos.
This scheme was modified by the various monotheisms that became dominant, so as to make God the source of our telos, to make this telos other-worldly (the Kingdom of God), and to make what Aristotle would have called vice or error into “sin.” But still, even after this transformation, ethical statements remain explicitly statements of fact: X is good because X will help you manifest your telos and is God’s plan for you.
Though the Christian philosophers thought that, since The Fall of Man, these facts were not available to us rationally, but only through the grace of God.
Later, the rationalists followed suit, and said that our reason is insufficient to choose our ends but is only suitable to choose means towards ends which are chosen in some other way (that “is”/“ought” thing).
Aristotle’s ethics has this structure: 1) Human beings are untutored; 2)
Human beings have a telos; 3) Ethics is the tutelage
necessary for human beings to achieve their telos.
Enlightenment philosophers abandoned the idea that there was such a thing as a
telos for human beings, and in so doing, lost the only way
of making ethical statements statements of fact. To Aristotle, an ethical
statement was true if the ethical rule it described did in fact help people
achieve their telos. Without reference to a
telos, ethical statements don’t mean anything at all.
So instead, enlightenment thinkers, who were okay with #1 (humans are untutored) and #3 (moral precepts are designed to correct human nature) stuck themselves with the impossible task of deriving #3 from #1. (Myself, I’m not sure this is quite as impossible as MacIntyre makes it out to be.
If I remember correctly, Aristotle didn’t start out with #2 as a premise, but derived it logically from his understanding of human nature, that is, from the same place he gets #1.
But in any case, MacIntyre says that the enlightenment thinkers did not want to saddle people with a telos, so perhaps it doesn’t matter whether or not it is derivable.)
The insistence that you cannot get an “ought” from an “is” that so perplexed
the moral philosophers is, MacIntyre insists, a bugbear that results from this
same undeclared premise: that humans have no telos, no
function, no purpose. For things with purposes, “is” may very well imply
“ought.” This is a watch; ergo it ought to tell the correct
time. A good watch tells the correct time; a bad watch is slow or fast or
right only twice a day. Good or bad for watches is embedded in the very
concept of watch. Similarly, if a person has a telos, he or
she may be more or less successful in meeting it, and his or her actions will
be more or less good, more or less ethical in Aristotelian terms, to the
extent that they assist in this attempt. And what these actions are is a
factual inquiry: is implies ought.
We still make our moral arguments and moral statements as if they had the form of falsifiable statements of fact, but we’ve lost the ability to articulate what makes them factual or falsifiable.
To try to fill in the gap, we’ve had to resort to a bunch of fictions.
For example, to replace teleology we have “utility”; to replace God’s revealed laws, we have the categorical imperative or “inalienable human rights” (or we continue to refer to God’s revealed laws but only in a way that makes them indistinguishable from the other merely emotive utterances of modern ethics).
These things are all just phantasmagorical placeholders that are designed to fill in the inconvenient and embarrassing gaps in moral theory, but that have no more real existence than do things like phlogiston or the luminiferous aether, which once served similar purposes in physics to the purposes “rights” and “utility” serve in modern ethical theories.
But still we continue to argue as though one of these gambits had succeeded
(though if we bother to investigate, we discover that none of them really
have). And yet we suspect that all of our moral discourse is a
machiavellian
struggle to manipulate and deceive each other. Our moral claims are
incommensurable because they have incompatible, largely fictional bases, and
so there is no reality or appeal to reality with which we can adjudicate
moral disputes.
This leads to petulant protest, a modern form of moral discourse, which is used because rational argument has no hope of succeeding.
The other dominant variety of moral discourse today is unmasking, in which foes discover each others’ moral pronouncements to be sham façades that mask selfish and arbitrary desires (hey, what do you know, Senator So-and-so is a hypocrite!).
This amounts to a parlor game, since everybody’s ethics have become incoherent and full of internal contradictions.
Along with such fictional devices as “right” and “utility,” the modern age
has created “effectiveness” as a fetish in moral argument. Effectiveness is
central to the character of the bureaucratic manager, who uses the myth of
managerial expertise to manipulate those being managed and to justify the
managers’ power. Like appeals to God, right, or utility, appeals to managerial
expertise disguise the ultimately expressive or imperative nature of the
utterance. The idea of managerial expertise implies a domain of real knowledge
about social structures and their inputs and outputs of which the manager has
specialized and true knowledge. This turns out to be a false claim. The basis
for managerial, bureaucratically-controlled societies (like ours) is that the
managers are thought to be value-neutral or value-independent, and actually
effective at assigning means to ends (though neither is really true).
The enlightenment also led to “fact”-based natural science and empiricism in general.
As part of this, the Aristotelian notion of ethics was split into two distinct philosophical disciplines: ethics (“what is good?”) and will (“how do intentions become actions?”).
Whereas in the Aristotelian view, explanations of human actions only make sense in reference to a hierarchy of goods and to the telos, in the mechanistic worldview, human action must be explained independently of any goods, intentions, purposes, reasons, or telos.
The social sciences of which managers are presumed to be experts are those in which the human subjects are seen in this manner.
This leads to a viewpoint from which it comes to appear as if the people being
manipulated by the practitioners of the social/managerial sciences do not have
any intention or purpose or telos of their own worth
respecting, but the same is implicitly not the case for the
manipulators and social scientists themselves, who must have intentions and
purposes for their actions to make any sense at all.
Social science (which includes economics) does not actually succeed, MacIntyre says, at deriving laws with predictive power.
Its “generalizations” are in no way scientific, but merely are dressed up like science.
This is because human affairs are systematically unpredictable, for several reasons: It is impossible in principle to predict the effects of the sorts of radically new conceptual innovations that occur in human history.
People cannot confidently predict even their own actions.
Chance trivialities can have large effects (what we would today call “the butterfly effect”).
Game-theory-like situations map poorly to real-life situations, and even so, they imply a necessary level of deceptiveness and recursive counter-plotting that makes real-world scientific observation and prediction difficult. (For example, during the Vietnam war, war-theorists working for the United States government cleverly created simulations and projections for victory using the best data they had at their disposal — data that was being systematically falsified by other elements of the same government who were using their own game-theory-ish reasons for using deceit in the service of victory.)
That said, there are some predictabilities in human behavior: There are some,
sometimes unconscious but justifiable, expectations of each others’ behavior
that allow us to engage in such social actions as scheduling and coordination.
There are statistical regularities in human action. Certain regularities of
nature place constraints on human possibility. Certain regularities of social
life also have predictive power (for instance, if your parents have more
money, you will probably have more educational opportunity).
People simultaneously want to make the world predictable (to assist in the success of their plans) and to make themselves unpredictable (to preserve their freedom).
For this reason, all we really should expect from social scientists are “usually”s.
Managerial pretensions to expertise (and thereby to the power and money that come with positions like President of the United States or Chief Executive Officer) are based on exaggerated and unfounded claims for the theoretical precision and accuracy of the social sciences.
When somebody claims to be doing something because of managerial expertise, you can be sure they are really just disguising their own desire or arbitrary preference, just the same as if they claimed to be fulfilling the will of god, maximizing utility, or respecting inalienable human rights.
Nonetheless, the contemporary vision of the world is bureaucratically
Weberian — Max Weber
mixed with Erving
Goffman. Goffman’s sociological point of view presupposes morals to be
false or at least irrelevant. It is honor, or the regard of others, that
takes its place as a motivator.
MacIntyre says that modern society found itself in much the same position as that of the Pacific islanders who had a set of taboos they were unable to explain to the missionaries and explorers who visited them.
Whatever reasons had originally led to the establishment of the taboos had long since vanished, and so all they could do when asked to explain their odd customs was to say, “but to do otherwise would be taboo.” MacIntyre says that Kamehameha Ⅱ was able to abolish the taboo system abruptly and by fiat precisely because it had no foundation underneath it anymore.
(I’m reminded of Hannah Arendt’s recollection of Nazi Germany as a time and
place where “…the few rules and standards according to which men used to tell
right from wrong, and which were invoked to judge or justify others and
themselves, and whose validity were supposed to be self-evident to every sane
person either as a part of divine or of natural law.… without much notice…
collapsed almost overnight, and then it was as though morality suddenly stood
revealed in the original meaning of the word, as a set of mores, customs and
manners, which could be exchanged for another set with hardly more trouble
than it would take to change the table manners of an individual or a people.”)
MacIntyre says that for those of us who have inherited the Western moral tradition, Nietzsche was our Kamehameha.
Nietzsche thought he was abolishing morality in general, but in fact, MacIntyre says, he was only pointing out the futility of the enlightenment project of providing a rational justification for the fragmentary remnants of classical ethics — our taboos.
If the classical ethical philosopher asked “what sort of person am I to
become, and how?” the modern ethical philosopher asked “what taboos must I
follow, and why?” It was a doomed project, because the taboos had become
dislodged from their original justifications, and the whole framework in which
those justifications made sense had been abandoned as part of the
enlightenment. To a modern philosopher like
John Rawls, for
instance, the virtues are nothing but tendencies to obey the taboos, with the
taboos being somehow more fundamental than the virtues.
What’s the alternative?
In the background of our struggles with moral philosophy and in the virtues we sympathize with but don’t understand enough to be able to justify, there is the ghost of an earlier and more coherent ethical system.
We may be able to retrace our steps and recover it.
The characteristics of “heroic” societies are revealed in the myths of
antiquity — not necessarily because these myths represent the realities of
the times they depict, but because the cultures that used and conveyed those
myths defined their own cultures in relation to them. In these societies,
everyone had a role and a purpose just by virtue of being born into a
particular station in a particular society with relations to particular
people. Nobody is defined by their “hidden depths” or their inner lives, but
by their actions relative to their roles; a person is what a person
does. Morality and social structure are the same thing; there isn’t
even a concept of morality as distinct from, independent of, or superior to
the particular social structure. You can’t “step outside” your society and
judge its moral system in comparison to some other system. Life is a
story that ends, tragically and in defeat, with death. A story like a
saga isn’t just incidentally a story about a life, but is a representation of
a life that is already understood to have the form of a story. Virtue is what
enables you to fulfill the role you have and to conduct yourself in your
story. Contra Nietzsche, the hero does not assert his arbitrary will, but
accepts his role as being a real thing worthy of respect; the self is not
self-created but is an incarnation or enacting of a socially-defined role.
This heroic background is refined by the Greeks in several ways, as by the fifth century B.C. it is possible to disagree about what is just (to Homer, justice was equivalent to what is in harmony with the prevailing order; later, you could ask the question “is what is in harmony with the prevailing order also just?”).
The tragedians (Sophocles in particular) focus on what happens when the moral system fails to cohere, producing contradictions.
A person has two contradictory ethical obligations that cannot be reconciled and the tragedy that results is just that there is no right way to proceed (for instance: my obligation arising from my role as a sister and my obligation arising from my role as the subject of a king come into conflict).
The sophists insist that virtues are relative, and the right way to proceed is whatever gets you what you’re after.
Plato, and later Aristotle, hope to show that the virtues don’t actually conflict and aren’t as flimsy as the sophists would have it.
From here, MacIntyre gives a recap of The Nicomachean Ethics, which, if you’ve been paying attention around here for the past few months, you shouldn’t need.
He says that this ethics tightly links moral virtue and practical intelligence, such that in the Aristotelian view, there is no place for actors like a fool whose heart is in the right place or a bureaucratic manager who is efficient at matching means to ends without care for what the ends are.
But there are problems with trying to bring Aristotle’s ethics into the modern era.
For one thing, Aristotle’s ethics requires a telos for human beings, but his idea of this telos was based on his now-ridiculous-seeming “metaphysical biology.” Also, if Aristotle’s virtues were closely tied to his particular society and to the roles available in it (as we have learned such virtues must be), how can these be relevant to us in our very different society today?
Furthermore, Aristotle views human life as perfectible — he thinks we can ultimately remove the conflicts from it (these conflicts are flaws); MacIntyre thinks it’s more likely that conflicts are more basic, and, like the tragedians concluded, are unavoidable and, well, tragic.
In the Middle-Ages, a fragmentary Aristotelian scheme of virtues was rediscovered, but interpreted through a filter of Christianity — one which was itself influenced by the stoic notion of virtue as a singular thing, detached from telos.
In this view, morally-right acting is solely a matter of will, and the results of the action and whatever virtues contribute to the action are incidental.
There is also an emphasis on the divine law, which is universal (not embedded in the polis or in some particular society).
Secular law had by this time lost any plausible connection to morality — it was no longer an expression of the desires of the polis, but the imposition of an empire.
By the 17th–18th centuries, virtues had lost their coherence altogether, and had come to be understood as a variety of altruism that we call upon to subdue our natural egoism in order to get along with each other.
This would have made no sense to Aristotle, who thought of the virtues as being motivated by self-love and as being at the same time inherently supportive of friendship and community.
Virtues also became mere inclinations to conform to moral laws, and, finally, got reduced from virtues to virtue, as in the stoic viewpoint.
The last great representative of the classical tradition of the virtues in
Western culture was, MacIntyre says,
Jane Austen, who did
this by recreating something akin to the Greek city-state in a fictional
upper-class family milieu.
Healthy, undecayed accounts of virtue have three things in common: a concept of practice, an idea of the narrative order of human life, and a moral tradition that develops out of these.
By “practice,” MacIntyre means some sort of occupation or activity that is
deliberate and well-defined and traditional at least to the extent where it
can involve internal goods — that is, rewards that exist only within
the practice itself and not in terms of what the practice enables you to gain
outside of it. For example, if you play chess well, the reward you get is the
internal good of having played a good chess game; if you are playing in order
to win a trophy, you are playing for the external good of the trophy, not the
internal good of playing well.
External goods are more zero-sum, more the objects of competition.
Internal goods are more about personal excellence; when we succeed in attaining internal goods, this tends not to detract from the good of those around us but to enhance them.
MacIntyre says that a virtue is that which enables us to achieve internal goods.
Practices are embodied in traditions that are kept alive by institutions. But
institutions are themselves focused on external goods. It is the
virtues that keep practices from being corrupted by their institutions
(particularly the virtues of justice, courage, and truthfulness). This doesn’t
mean that all practices are good. Nor does it mean that any practice and
associated set of virtues is as good as any other (for that would lead us back
to the same problem as our current catastrophe). When you see that life has a
telos and therefore there is a practice of life, you see
that life itself has its virtues — you can extrapolate from your idea of the
internal rewards of a practice to the idea of The Good in life as a whole. In
this way the idea of a practice and the understanding of the narrative nature
of human life lead to the development of a coherent moral tradition.
The modern view of life makes this difficult.
Life is divided into stages and further into roles (“work-life” and “home-life” for instance), and we are encouraged to view behaviors atomistically rather than seeing our lives as unified and ourselves as engaged in large-scale narratives.
But human activity is intelligible and our actions are
within a narrative context of history and goals. An action isn’t just part of
a narrative but is part of many narratives from many points of view.
These narratives are unpredictable (what happens next?) but that
doesn’t mean they lack telos or that the
telos is merely retrospectively assigned. The only way I can
answer the question “what am I to do?” is if I can answer the question “what
stories am I a part of?”
The way I read this is that when you ask yourself whether or not you are behaving ethically right, you are trying to justify yourself.
You justify yourself by accounting for your behavior, that is to say, telling its story, putting it in a narrative context complete with its telos.
By doing this you create a context in which the virtues will shine forth as the sort of excellences of character that advance you to your telos.
MacIntyre says that the quest is a form of narrative in which the
character of the protagonist and his telos become more
sharply defined over time. You start off with a vague idea of The Good, and
your experiences over the course of the quest make it clearer what The Good
must be. The virtues are what equip us for success in the quest.
But your narrative, whatever it is, doesn’t start from a blank slate.
You start in a social context that may equip you with obligations, debts, and expectations of various sorts right from the get-go.
You cannot define yourself independently of these, though you have the choice of defining yourself either in agreement with or in rebellion against any of it.
We are all protagonists of the tragic variety, in that we will inevitably encounter irreconcilable ethical obligations.
That said, though we cannot solve the dilemmas we encounter, we can navigate them more or less skillfully.
The concept of virtue MacIntyre has described was destroyed, he says, by the
cult of bureaucratic individualism that emerged from
the
enlightenment. Employees, for example, do not typically engage in a
practice associated with internal goods (they are motivated by salary or other
external goods); the typical modern person is not a practitioner but a
spectator/consumer, engaged in what MacIntyre calls “institutional
acquisitiveness” or “aesthetic consumption”
(consumerism, I think
they call it these days).
Today, people in our culture are unable to weigh conflicting claims of justice because they are inherently incommensurable. John Rawls and Robert Nozick, for example, represent sophisticated philosophical justifications of something akin to popular quasi-socialist liberal and property-rights libertarian perspectives, respectively.
MacIntyre notes that even if you accept either or both of their arguments as valid, this resolves nothing, since it is their premises that are incompatible.
(Interestingly, neither Rawls nor Nozick relies on the concept of
desert, which
is central in the popular versions of justice they are trying to
provide philosophical support for. MacIntyre says that this is because desert
requires a preexisting social context in order to make sense, and the thought
experiments that Rawls and Nozick rely on assume atomistic individuals without
preexisting communities or agreements on what is good. The popular notion of
desert, MacIntyre says, is yet another remnant of premodern justice that
shines through the cracks left after the catastrophe.)
Because there is no common ground on which disagreements about justice and morality can be argued, “modern politics is civil war carried on by other means” — nothing but power masked by rhetoric.
But this is not because Nietzsche has disproved morality.
He successfully defeated the various enlightenment projects of justifying morality, but he left the Aristotelian ethical framework unscathed.
The virtue tradition implies a rejection of the primacy of market values, the
cult of bureaucratic individualism, and acquisitiveness. It indicts the modern
political order (perhaps government in the abstract can be justified, but no
existing government can).
What to do about it?
Our task in this post-catastrophe world, MacIntyre says, is to construct “local forms of community within which civility and the intellectual and moral life can be sustained through the new dark ages which are already upon us.
And if the tradition of the virtues was able to survive the horrors of the last dark ages, we are not entirely without grounds for hope.
This time however the barbarians are not waiting beyond the frontiers; they have already been governing us for quite some time.”
After I gave such an enthusiastic recap of Alasdair MacIntyre’s After Virtue yesterday, and after spending much of the last several months studying, summarizing, and commenting on The Nicomachean Ethics, I hate to admit it, but virtue ethics has still kind of got me flummoxed.
We cannot base our ethics on the will of God because there is no God to will anything, or, at any rate, his believers seem to each have their own ideas of what this will might be, rendering it effectively arbitrary and no guidance at all.
We cannot base our ethics on utility, because utility is no basis at all but is itself an arbitrary evaluation that implies a preexisting ethics.
We cannot base our ethics on inherent rights and duties because these things too do not exist but are just shorthand ways of, again, stating our unbased preferences.
You can, I suppose, embrace this and consider it a feature, not a bug: ethics are nothing but arbitrarily-chosen preferences?
Well then, I’m going to arbitrarily choose some marvelous ones!
Horray for the freedom of choice!
But MacIntyre held out the possibility that ethics are not arbitrary at all but that they follow logically from the telos of being human.
This telos isn’t to be found in our biology, the way Aristotle thought you could look at a species and determine what it was uniquely designed to do and therefore discern its telos (humans are uniquely designed to reason, therefore to reason is our telos).
Instead, MacIntyre says, it is the web of socially-defined relationships that we are cast into by accident of birth that determine the stories we inhabit, and these stories encode our tele; ethics follows and is defined as those virtues that will enable us to succeed in playing the roles in these stories well.
But he also said that you still have to use your freedom to decide which stories are your stories and how you are going to play your role: you may find yourself in the role of a prince, but that still doesn’t tell you whether you’re the prince who is going to kill the king and rule the kingdom, the prince who is going to renounce the throne and marry his beloved, or the prince who is going to sit under the Bo tree until he reaches enlightenment.
That said, you pretty certainly don’t want to be the prince who has a sudden loss of nerve and flees the battlefield in surrender, the prince whose flighty indecision turns his family into intriguers, or the prince who lets his kingdom go to hell because he’d rather work on his butterfly collection than on pressing matters of state.
Although the virtues may not be able to decide between the radically different options available to you, they may help equip you both to choose wisely and to follow through on your choice in such a way that your story turns out successfully.
But isn’t choosing your story and defining the criteria of success no less arbitrary and indefensible than any of the other bases for ethics that have been proposed?
The first person who suggested that a story of a prince who renounced his throne to seek for enlightenment (or to marry a commoner, or what have you) was a story of a successful prince, was someone who was inventing and defending (emotively!) an arbitrary ethics, no less than the first person to say that all men are endowed by their creator with certain inalienable rights.
It wasn’t until 2020 that I got around to reading G.E.M.
Anscombe’s “Modern Moral Philosophy.” She seems to have sooner detected the central problem that MacIntyre examined in his later book (Anscombe’s essay was published in 1958): “[T]he concepts of obligation, and duty — moral obligation and moral duty, that is to say — and of what is morally right and wrong, and of the moral sense of ‘ought,’ ought to be jettisoned if this is psychologically possible; because they are survivals, or derivatives from survivals, from an earlier conception of ethics which no longer generally survives, and are only harmful without it.”
I admit I was a little surprised — I think I had associated the Dalai Lama with some of his more foggy-headed, romantic, guru-seeking fans here in California and so I approached his book with preconceptions of it being likely to be a bunch of gauzy platitudes dressed up with Buddhist nomenclature and foisted off as profundity.
Instead, the book was largely methodical and precise, and also refreshingly practical in a way that many modern books on ethics are not.
I recently read his earlier book, Ethics for the New Millennium (), and, alas, it was more along the lines of what I had been afraid Beyond Religion was going to be.
Still, there was some meat on the bone worth chewing on.
The key to Ethics for the New Millennium is the Dalai Lama’s assertion that the way to be happy and content is to develop and expand one’s own compassion.
The purest and most universally-directed altruism is simultaneously the most enlightened self-interest.
Similarly, the key to solving the variety of the world’s problems is for the people directly involved in the problems and their solutions to develop and nurture compassion in themselves — if they do this, the solutions will come of themselves; if they fail to attend to this, then no programs they come up with, however clever, will do the trick.
Because, according to the Dalai Lama, the happiness/suffering continuum is the primary (or even only) human motivator — as people come to understand that their happiness depends on compassion and on the happiness of others, a sort of virtuous cycle will lift all of us up into more rewarding lives.
To me, all of this is suspiciously nice-sounding, as in “wouldn’t it be nice if that were true.”
But do we have any reason to believe that it is true, or are we just inclined to believe it because it sounds comforting?
For example, is it really accurate to say that people are motivated by a one-dimensional happiness/suffering continuum?
Might it not really be the case that human motivations are multi-dimensional, and that these motivations might be pulling us in different directions at once — some towards less suffering and more happiness, and some just the opposite?
People are driven by status and shame, eroticism and disgust, fear and pride, and so many other things besides, and at least some of these seem to map only awkwardly to the happiness/suffering continuum.
And is it really true that by cultivating compassion and empathy and exhibiting altruistic behavior that we inevitably become happier and more content?
This may sound cynical, but I think there may be a confusion of cause and effect here.
I know that when I am being compassionate, empathetic, and altruistic I am also usually happy and content — but might it be that when my own needs are met, when my life overflows with abundance, when I have few worries and cares, then I am most able to concentrate on other people’s needs and take the time to attend to them?
It may be that my happiness and contentment and my compassion and altruism stem from a common precondition of being carefree and satisfied.
(When I put on my amateur sociobiologist’s pith helmet, I get even more cynical about this: conspicuously altruistic acts are a great way of demonstrating fitness to potential mates.
They’re kind of like feathers in a peacock’s tail: “Look at how much surplus I have in my life, that I can spend so much time, energy, and/or money on the lives of other people!
I must be a mighty successful fellow!”)
One thing I thought was interesting was the Dalai Lama’s suggestion that people use something akin to creative visualization to develop compassion.
In a similar way to the way athletes will imagine themselves succeeding in particular athletic feats, and this act of vivid imagination will help to train their minds and bodies to cooperate in actually accomplishing these feats, the Dalai Lama suggests that we can improve our compassion by “sustained reflection on, and familiarization with compassion, through rehearsal and practice”.
Now while generally translated simply as “compassion,” the term nying je has a wealth of meaning that is difficult to convey succinctly… It connotes love, affection, kindness, gentleness, generosity of spirit, and warm-heartedness… [I]t does not imply “pity” as the word compassion may.
There is no sense of condescension.
On the contrary, nying je denotes a feeling of connection with others, reflecting its origins in empathy.…
…[It] is understood as an emotion, [but] it belongs to that category of emotions which have a more developed cognitive component.
Some emotions, such as the revulsion we tend to feel at the sight of blood, are basically instinctual.
Others, such as fear of poverty, have this more developed cognitive component.
We can thus understand nying je in terms of a combination of empathy and reason.
We can think of empathy as the characteristic of a very honest person; reason as that of someone who is very practical.
When the two are put together, the combination is highly effective.
The process of developing nying je and of disciplining those emotions and tendencies that interfere with it, is a life-long one:
This is no easy task, and those who are religiously minded must understand that there is no blessing or initiation — which, if only we could receive it — or any mysterious or magical formula or mantra or ritual — if only we could discover it — that can enable us to achieve transformation instantly.
It comes little by little, just as a building is constructed brick by brick or, as the Tibetan expression has it, an ocean is formed drop by drop.
Also, because, unlike our bodies which soon get sick, old, and worn out, the afflictive [harm-provoking] emotions never age, it is important to realize that dealing with them is a lifelong struggle.
Nor should the reader suppose that what we are talking about here is the mere acquisition of knowledge.
It is not even a question of developing the conviction that may come from such knowledge.
What we are talking about is gaining an experience of virtue through constant practice and familiarization so that it becomes spontaneous.
What we find is that the more we develop concern for others’ well-being, the easier it becomes to act in others’ interests.
As we become habituated to the effort required, so the struggle to sustain it lessens.
Eventually, it will become second nature.
But there are no shortcuts.
The New York Times published an interesting piece on “Raising a Moral Child” that spotlights some of the current thinking on how children learn to become ethically engaged.
The summary is that it is important to praise and guide children with an eye to making them value their own characters and to understand how their behaviors form their characters.
Another data point that suggests the practical value of an Aristotle-style “virtue ethics” approach.
Those of us committed to fomenting tax resistance would be wise to keep our eyes on the research of those committed to encouraging tax compliance, as their conclusions often have mirror-images that will be useful to us.
The latest in this series is a paper by Richard Lavoie entitled Vox Clamantis in Deserto: The Role of the Individual in Forging a Strong Duty to the Tax System.
Excerpt:
Societies exhibiting high tax morale typically maintain stable levels of
high tax compliance over time (establishing a societal “taxpaying
ethos”) as these underlying foundational attitudes become enshrined as
self-maintaining social norms. However, if the underlying social norms
begin to erode over time, a society historically exhibiting a strong
taxpaying ethos can quickly flip into a non-compliant one once a tipping
point is reached.
With the exception of some aberrational sub-groups, the United States
typifies a society with a strong taxpaying ethos. However, in recent
decades the social norms forming the foundation of this ethos appear to
have weakened. Scandals at the Service have weakened its public image.
The rise of the tea party movement has questioned the efficacy and role
of government, as well as promoting the highly questionable proposition
that Americans are currently “overtaxed.” Politicians, who should defend
the government that they were elected to run, often act to undermine its
legitimacy and advocate for steep spending cuts in addition to tax
reductions.
These forces, among others, threaten the very foundations of our tax
system by undermining our historical societal faith in the fairness of
our tax system and the obligation to fund necessary government services.
The Tax Foundation has drawn up a map that purports to show how cigarette smuggling in the United States is correlated to the tobacco tax rates in those states.
So, for instance: “New York is the highest net importer of smuggled cigarettes, totaling 56.9 percent of the total cigarette market in the state.
New York also has the highest state cigarette tax ($4.35 per pack), not counting the local New York City cigarette tax (an additional $1.50 per pack).
Smuggling in New York has risen sharply since 2006 (+59 percent), as has the tax rate (+190 percent).”
The phone security consultants “pindrop” have done some back-of-the-envelope calculations on the massive ongoing criminal operation in which American immigrants are shaken down over the phone by people masquerading as IRS agents. They estimate that 450,000 people were targeted by this scam in alone.
Pindrop also posted their analysis of how the scam works, and even some excerpts from a recording of one of the calls.
Thoreau’s Walden, (Wikipedia summarizes,) “is a reflection upon simple living in natural surroundings” — a sort of memoir or collection of observations on man and nature, a celebration of the placid and the wild with a dose of wry skepticism about civilization.
Sound about right?
Philip Cafaro thinks we’ve been miscategorizing (and underestimating) Walden by treating it as though it were merely some sort of romantic pastoral meditation, when in fact Thoreau intended it as a challenging book of practical, experimental philosophy.
The confusion comes because Thoreau was trying to extend a classical form of ethical philosophy that had gone out of fashion — to the extent that it had almost become unrecognizable.
It was only after the virtue ethics revival of recent decades that Thoreau’s work could be appreciated for what it is.
“Because Walden is a work in virtue ethics,” Cafaro writes, “it is hard for some readers — and most contemporary philosophers — to see it as a work of ethics at all.”
Thoreau meant his book to show him trying to work out his ethical philosophy in practice, and so it discusses ethical questions in terms of concrete and specific means and ends and alternatives, and of real-life examples of choices he and his neighbors made.
“Ironically, however,” Cafaro writes, “this comprehensiveness and specificity make it harder for most academic philosophers to recognize Walden as a genuine work in ethical philosophy, since contemporary ethical philosophy usually remains at a high level of generality and theoretical abstractness.”
Thoreau’s Walden retreat was not primarily from a “back to nature” impulse, but from a need to give himself enough space and breathing room to work out for himself how to live life best, without the hobbles of habit and cultural conformity.
“I went into the woods,” Thoreau says, “because I wished to live deliberately, to front only the essential facts of life, and see if I could not learn what it had to teach, and not, when I came to die, discover that I had not lived.”
“I wanted to live deep and suck out all the marrow of life,” he continues.
Which is to say, Cafaro believes, Thoreau wanted a flourishing life, or, as Aristotle would put it, a life of eudaimonia.
Thoreau had little patience for the small ethics of thou-shalt-nots and duties to our neighbors; he wanted to explore the big ethics that included such things but only as side effects of the project of flourishing and becoming a better person and sucking the marrow out of life.
Ethics is not limited to a category of life, thought Thoreau, but: “Our whole life is startlingly moral.
There is never an instant’s truce between virtue and vice.”
Cafaro believes Thoreau was not only reawakening the ancient virtue ethics tradition, but was also trying to modernize and extend it.
Among his contributions here was an attempt to make virtue ethics more democratic.
Virtue ethics by its nature is impatient with the sort of “everyone’s a winner” denial of individual merit and championing of mediocrity that democracy sometimes encourages; but while ancient virtue ethics tends to be directed toward the aristocracy and to concern itself with the virtues of the ruling class, Thoreau’s virtue ethics is more down-to-earth and available to everyone.
Another addition Thoreau makes to the virtue ethics tradition is to incorporate an environmental consciousness into it: to make our relationship with the natural environment, and the health of that environment, a core component of human flourishing, and to promote respect for the flourishing of nature on its own terms (some of the virtues Thoreau praises are exemplified in his book by the behavior of animals, for example the “admirable virtue” of fish trying in vain to spawn up human-dammed streams).
Cafaro goes so far as to call Walden “a fully developed and inspiring environmental virtue ethics” — an extension of the virtue ethics tradition that makes it especially important today.
Thoreau also insists that the virtues must be developed by the individual and for the individual.
There isn’t a one-size-fits-all package or a single destiny or highest calling for everyone.
We each need to build the virtues appropriate for ourselves, and this is something we have to do through real-world experimentation and practice (in several places in Walden he writes of what he is doing as an “experiment”).
This, too, contrasts with the mix of theorizing and empirical observation in the Aristotelian tradition.
Thoreau also tries to reclaim the virtues from their ongoing appropriation by capitalism.
He was living at a time when terms like…
“profit”
(“For what is a man profited, if he shall gain the whole world, and lose his own soul?” — the Bible)
“career”
(“Rest is not quitting / The busy career, / Rest is the fitting / Of self to one’s sphere.” — John Sullivan Dwight)
“industry”
(“…people that trust wholly to other’s charity, and without industry of their own, will be always poor.” — William Temple)
“enterprise”
(“The success of any great moral enterprise does not depend upon numbers.” — William Lloyd Garrison)
“economy”
(“Beauty rests on necessities. The line of beauty is the result of perfect economy.” — Ralph Waldo Emerson)
…which had included, but not been exclusive to, connotations about money, finance, corporate behavior, accounting, and the like, began to be almost completely taken over by those uses.
Thoreau pointedly and often ironically uses terms like these to try, in Cafaro’s words, “to remoralize America’s economic discourse [and] to moralize his own economic life and the lives of his readers.”
Thoreau, of course, was also a political thinker, and his contributions to political philosophy are also, I think, misunderstood and undervalued.
Cafaro also discusses these, but I think his insight is weaker here.
Rather than wrestling with the thoroughly radical and severe challenge of Thoreau’s actual political views, Cafaro seems to prefer to wish Thoreau had more ordinarily progressive ones, and then to criticize him for his failure to adequately justify these imagined points of view.
Thoreau complained that “There are nowadays professors of philosophy, but not philosophers… To be a philosopher is not merely to have subtle thoughts, nor even to found a school, but so to love wisdom as to live according to its dictates, a life of simplicity, independence, magnanimity, and trust.
It is to solve some of the problems of life, not only theoretically, but practically.”
Thoreau’s work I think has made philosophers of many of his readers; and Cafaro’s may well help to make philosophers of some professors of philosophy.
A few days back I visited a local memorial to the “first responders” who were
killed in the 9/11 attacks. The memorial — called “Standing Tall” — was
installed several blocks from my home at a fire station, and features a ring of
tall rods, each painted either red or blue and symbolizing a fire or police
department member who was killed. Inside the ring is a bare girder that had
been part of one of the buildings that was destroyed in the attacks.
In the concrete base of the ring are several words that I interpreted as
representing the virtues exemplified by those killed, or maybe more abstractly
the virtues we are to expect from those in the positions they held:
I asked the groundskeeper if he knew why these nineteen words were selected
for the memorial, but he didn’t know, and the Google hasn’t gotten me any
further. The conceptual design documents for the sculpture don’t list the
words or give any indication of how they were chosen. None of the news articles
about the unveiling of the sculpture mention them at all. They’re a strange mix
of nouns and adjectives, which makes me wonder if they might have been
extracted from some other source rather than being selected deliberately and
independently.
Why these virtues in particular? Why courage and valor, for
instance. Doesn’t valor imply courage? What distinguishes them? Is valor a
more public-facing courage? Or does valor imply seeking out and deliberately
confronting those important things that are most dangerous, while courage just
means facing dangerous things bravely when you happen to encounter them?
Why kindness, compassion, and consideration — why did that set of
virtues in particular need to be mapped out with three words’ worth of
precision? Can there be commitment and reliability without diligence? integrity
without honesty? What does forbearance add in addition to the combination of
strength and courage?
These aren’t criticisms, but just some of the thoughts that came to mind as I
meditated over the list. I think there may be something to be gained from
engaging with lists like these rather than treating them as platitudes and
nodding solemnly at them (yes that’s a good word, and that’s a good word…).
What are the virtues? Are some more fundamental than others, forming the base
that others derive from? Are there virtues we don’t have names for yet? Are
there attitudes, or sentiments, or tendencies that are even more fundamental
than the virtues, and if we figure those out the rest of the virtues will just
come naturally?
Here are a couple more lists: the “four cardinal virtues” of ancient Greece,
and Aristotle’s more expansive
list:
What first jumps out at me when I put these side-by-side is how much Aristotle
improved on the cardinal virtues by adding ones that are conducive to people
living together joyfully: things like wittiness, friendship, amiability, good
temper, liberality, and sincerity. I hadn’t thought of Aristotle as being so
concerned with such things, but this shows he really stretched things in that
direction.
He also I think does us a service by emphasizing the intellectual
virtues as virtues, and not as we commonly do today: as hobbies and
quirks (people who are good at trivia or at Scrabble, or eccentrics), as
occupational skills (people with programming skills or a medical degree), or as
suspicious and anti-social tendencies.
To know the difference between a good argument and a bad one, to understand
basic facts about the world around you, to know about the biases and cognitive
illusions we’re all prone to (and how to resist them) — these are important
skills to have in order to be a good person. People who neglect to develop
these skills because they think they’re unimportant, optional, or
unfashionable, become worse people as a result.
another set of virtues, found over the doorway to the Salvation Army
building a couple of blocks from my front door
Some more lists of virtues:
Ayn Rand was a big Aristotle-head, but she apparently trimmed her list down to
three: “Rationality, Productiveness, Pride.”
When I read the Dalai Lama’s books on ethics (see ♇
12 February and
14 September 2012) I wasn’t doing so
with lists of virtues in mind, but in retrospect some that he seemed to focus
on included “inner resilience,” “purpose,” “connectedness,” “nying je”
(a sort of compassion for which there isn’t a good English translation),
“discernment,” “heedfulness,” “mindfulness,” “awareness,” “nonviolence,”
“altruism,” “patience,” “self-discipline,” and “generosity.”
Then there are virtues from the Christian tradition. Here are some:
The Three Christian Virtues (Paul)
The Fruit of the Spirit (Paul)
The Seven Christain Virtues (Prudentius)
Faith
Hope
Charity (love)
Love
Joy
Peace
Forbearance
Kindness
Goodness
Faith
Meekness
Temperance
Somewhere along the line I found “The Seven Virtues of Bushido” according to
Nitobe Inazo. These are those:
rectitude
courage
benevolence
respect
honesty
honor
loyalty
And all of this reminded me of when I was a boy and I had to memorize The Boy
Scout Law in order to become a certified Tenderfoot or some such thing. I still
know it by heart. “A scout is…”:
trustworthy
loyal
helpful
friendly
courteous
kind
obedient
cheerful
thrifty
brave
clean
reverent
There are some things that didn’t show up on any of these lists and I wonder
why, like “curiosity,” “willingness to try new things,” “initiative,”
“flexibility/adaptability,” “cooperativeness,” or “gratitude.”
Blessed are the peacemakers, perhaps, but if there is a virtue corresponding to
the tendency to intervene in situations to defuse tension and make them more
peaceful, I don’t know its name. “Conciliativeness” maybe? The sort of person
who tries to keep arguments from turning into fist fights and who reconciles
friends who’ve become angry with each other — don’t they deserve a virtue to
call their own?
And then there are other qualities, like “enthusiastic,” “good in bed,”
“decisive,” “steadfast,” “enterprising,” “visionary,” “tolerant,”
“influential,” or “unflappable,” that seem to form such a big part of our
pop-cultural sense of whether someone is admirable or not, but that you rarely
see on lists like this.
More useful, I suppose, would be the question of what happens after
you’ve identified a good set of virtues: how do you then develop them in
yourself (or maybe in yourself and others). What parts of this process are
pretty much the same across the virtues, and what parts are specific to
particular virtues? How much of this can you do on your own with diligent
effort, and for how much do you need a tutor of some sort? Can you teach an
old dog new virtues, or are some virtues habits you need to get in to while
you’re still young?
But this is as far as I’ve gotten today.
I neglected to include Benjamin Franklin’s list when I first compiled this set, but I’ll make up for that now:
Here is what I came up with (revised since I first posted it as a comment at Claire’s Living Freedom blog):
First, Character: the “Metavirtue”
I think there’s a prerequisite to my twelve virtues that’s a kind of umbrella over all of them — a “meta-virtue” maybe — that might be called character but requires more from me than just having character in a passive, descriptive sense.
It means I must value my character, be invested in it, see it as an end in itself.
So this is not to be confused with “reputation,” which is sort of like character, but only as a means to an end.
I considered honor and nobility (divorced from its hereditary aristocracy connotations) as possible synonyms for this virtue.
If I have character, this fortifies the rest of the virtues that I try to develop.
Without it, the other virtues may fail me when I need them most, because they will lack foundation.
My Twelve Virtues
I chose these as my twelve specific virtues to aspire to build on this foundation of character:
The Intellectual Virtues
curiosity
rationality
know-how
The “Core” Virtues
moderation
endurance
courage
fitness
The Social Virtues
rectitude
generosity
amiability
humility
cooperation
Curiosity
To be a virtuous person, I must make myself aware of how the world is and how it works, and the drive to do this is curiosity.
It helps when I can be mindfully aware rather than lost-in-thought, and open-minded so I don’t inadvertently filter out the very parts of reality that I can best learn from.
Curiosity also means inquisitiveness and skepticism: I don’t want to believe but to understand.
When I’m curious, I’m also exercising imagination so as to try out new possibilities for understanding the world, and this leads also to creativity and inventiveness as I imagine ways of changing or reinterpreting this world.
Curiosity and awareness also show themselves as vigilance and heedfulness.
These allow me to anticipate occasions that will require something of me, prepare myself for them, and keep my eyes peeled for opportunities and dangers.
Rationality
To engage with the world well and virtuously, I need to understand how the world works.
This means holding tight to what is really true, and fighting against the many temptations to believe what just isn’t so.
This is a lifelong project, so rationality also requires intellectual growth.
It also requires testing ideas against empirical reality with a scientific mindset and (when combined with curiosity) deductive skill.
Know-how
For some skills, there’s no substitute for getting your hands dirty and learning by doing.
Technology and affluence can make us helpless if we’re not careful.
I am more virtuous the more well-rounded I can become in art, craft, and general know-how.
Moderation
When I value my character, this helps me to not take pleasure from vices (anti-virtues).
Moderation goes the next step and helps me to not wholly forget myself in pleasure, even when that pleasure comes from virtuous or indifferent things.
A temperate person appreciates and enjoys the pleasures of life without getting lost in pursuit of them.
Moderation also tempers other emotions: preventing anger from easily boiling over into rage, for instance.
When I’m temperate, I also have balance in my life, and I have my priorities straight.
Moderation also guides me towards a life of simplicity, as I’m more able to live life well if I’m not pulled in many directions at once and I don’t have to shepherd too many possessions.
Similarly, the more I can trend toward serenity or at least calmness, the better grounding I will have from which to practice the other virtues without getting distracted.
Endurance
Endurance means working through pain, difficulty, boredom, and frustration.
It includes resilience, persistence, patience, and forbearance.
Combined with the serenity that comes from moderation, it can display itself as an attractive unflappability.
When persistence is combined with the inventiveness that comes from curiosity, it becomes adaptability.
Endurance comes to the assistance of the other virtues by helping me to stick to them when the going gets rough.
If I can adopt the advice of the Stoics, and see the various slings and arrows of outrageous fortune as opportunities to practice endurance, this will also help me to endure such things with more serenity.
Courage
While endurance helps me deal with current hardships, courage helps me with the fear of future hardships.
When combined with generosity, it can even rise to the level of valor, occasionally encouraging me to put myself in harm’s way by seeking out dragons that need to be slain.
When combined with the intellectual virtues, courage helps me to know which risks are worth taking and then to take them unflinchingly.
Fitness
We’re each dealt a hand not of our choosing when it comes to the state of our bodies and our health.
But we all can play this hand better or worse.
I respect the virtue of fitness when I take care of my body and try to keep it strong and able.
This in turn helps me be more able to practice the other virtues.
Rectitude
I practice rectitude when I’m honest with myself and others, when I’m sincere in my speech and earnest in my endeavors.
This virtue encourages me to be a man of my word: trustworthy and reliable.
I try also to know my duty irrespective of any explicit promises I have made: to be responsible and diligent.
I also want to be someone who can be trusted not to practice favoritism or self-dealing but to exercise a well-honed sense of justice.
I also put Aristotle’s “quasi-virtue” of shame under this heading.
Shame enables me to know when I’ve fallen short of the standards of rectitude, and gives me visceral feedback that helps me learn to be better.
Curiosity, moderation, and endurance help me to investigate and hone my sense of shame, so I am not shamed by things that are not really shameful.
Generosity
Generosity is my desire to give more than I take.
It means that I strive to be self-reliant (for which know-how and fitness help) and independent when I can be.
From that base, it is easier for me to be charitable: to take delight in giving to others or to enriching the commons.
I hope to cultivate virtues like ambition, industriousness, enterprise, productiveness, and initiative so I can boost my positive effect on the world around me (though I often struggle here with the vice of sloth, and also fear of sticking my neck out).
On rare occasions my generosity can even blossom into something approaching magnificence(in the Aristotelian sense).
Amiability
I aspire to be pleasant to be around, to be a note of harmony in social situations, and to elevate those around me.
I want to respect and to strive to understand other people, with sympathy, compassion, and consideration.
I want to demonstrate kindness, courtesy, and gratitude.
I want to contribute to warmth, joy, hope, wit, good humor, and cheer.
Humility
Conscious of my faults and of the many times I have fallen short, I strive to be humble, which I think will also encourage me to be tolerant and forgiving.
I want to seek out and discover the best in other people, as well as the strongest parts of opposing arguments and viewpoints, rather than trying to prove myself and my points of view to be superior by ferreting out the worst things around me to compare with.
I should remind myself to temper my sense of justice with mercy.
I ought to tread lightly when I am tempted to meddle in any business that isn’t my own.
Cooperation
I want to share in projects and activities with others in a way that promotes cooperation.
I need to be a team player when that is called for, and to strive to be conciliatory and peace-promoting rather than sowing discord or trash talking for low stakes.
I want to be a role model for others, and a mentor when I can be.
When a leader is needed, I want to be able to step into that role competently and to be able to command respect and confidence from those who follow my lead.
I want to nurture the virtues in those around me and to be helpful and encouraging to others in their projects.
Back in I gushed and gushed about Alasdair MacIntyre’s book After Virtue.
I’m not taking any of that gushing back today — I still think it was an exciting argument and one that has continued to resonate with me.
But this week I finally got around to reading G.E.M.
Anscombe’s essay “Modern Moral Philosophy,” which predates MacIntyre’s book by two decades, and I found that she had already put forward much of the core of MacIntyre’s later argument there.
MacIntyre only mentions Anscombe’s essay in a brief parenthetical in his book (in which he says that parts of his own argument are “both deeply indebted to and rather different from that of Anscombe 1958”).
To me it feels more like MacIntyre further elaborated a project and a theoretical framework that Anscombe deserves credit for establishing.
I’ll try to summarize her 26-page argument in sixteen paragraphs, in the hopes of whetting your appetite for reading the whole thing:
Anscombe argues that concepts like “moral obligation,” “morally right and wrong,” and “the moral sense of ‘ought’ ” have lost their meaning.
Such phrases “ought to be jettisoned” by philosophers “because they are survivals, or derivatives from survivals, from an earlier conception of ethics which no longer generally survives” and so are now just confusing.
(This is not because she is a moral nihilist — she’s about as far from that as you can get — but because she thinks philosophy has become hopelessly confused and needs to reset.)
She traces the term “moral” to Aristotle (if I remember right, Aristotle used ἠθικός which got translated into moralis in Latin).
But because of how the meaning of “moral” has shifted over time, to read Aristotle in translation today means to “constantly feel like someone whose jaws have somehow got out of alignment: the teeth don’t come together in a proper bite.”
Words like “should”/“ought”/“needs” are used in two senses:
First, to describe the requirements for things with purposes (this machinery needs oil, ought to be oiled); secondly, in the modern moral sense to indicate obligation.
This second sense has a historical pedigree.
Anscombe believes it resulted from the Judeo-Christian belief in divine law.
Christianity borrowed terms from Greek philosophy and put a divine law spin on them, so that, for example, the Greek word for going astray or being mistaken (ἀμαρτάνειν) became the word for sinning: breaking the divine law.
When Christianity changed the meanings of concepts like sin and virtue in this way, they made moral terms like “should” and “ought” appropriate to them.
But over time moral philosophy shed divine law but tried to keep the virtues.
In doing so, it found that this foundation had been pulled out from under them.
If moderns continue to talk about virtues in terms of “should” and “ought” without the Christian appendages that those terms could successfully attach to, they’re talking empty nonsense.
Anscombe calls this “the survival of a concept outside the framework of thought that made it a really intelligible one” that has had the effect of rendering “[the] word ‘ought’… a word of mere mesmeric force.… a word retaining the suggestion of force, and apt to have a strong psychological effect, but which no longer signifies a real concept at all.”
European ethical philosophers of note have tied themselves in knots trying to make sense of the moral ought.
Butler put “conscience” first, “but appears ignorant that a man’s conscience may tell him to do the vilest things.”
Hume was “a mere — brilliant — sophist” who removed ethical judgments from the category of things that can be true.
Kant establishes the “absurd” idea of “legislating for oneself” and takes it to uselessly rigid conclusions.
Bentham and Mill (whose utilitarianism was “stupid”) got lost in a thicket of “pleasure” as an end, though not because of a supposed “naturalistic fallacy” about which Anscombe “do[es] not find accounts of it coherent.”
Sidgwick and Moore are what Anscombe calls consequentialists — using a term that is now standard, but that she herself coined for this essay.
She means the term to describe someone who reasons more or less like a utilitarian but without necessarily specifying “utility” as the criterion — someone who believes that we are acting ethically if and only if we are acting to optimize some quality or other of the future state of the world.
Sidgwick in particular advanced a theory of responsibility that Anscombe says was particularly seductive and harmful.
In brief, that theory is this: “it does not make any difference to a man’s responsibility for an effect of his action which he can foresee, that he does not intend” that effect.
There is something to this idea, which is what makes it so seductive, but left as-is and not examined further it can have terrible consequences.
The terrible consequences in this case turned out to include consequentialism.
If you blindly follow Sidgwick’s idea to its logical conclusions, those conclusions are of the ends-justify-the-means variety:
It is justified to do the most shameful awful vile thing, if an unintended but foreseeable hypothetical consequence of not doing it is sufficiently bad.
Furthermore, “you can exculpate yourself from the actual consequences of the most disgraceful actions, so long as you can make out a case for having not foreseen them.”
(Anscombe suggests a more sensible formula wold be this: “[A] man is responsible for the bad consequences of his bad actions, but gets no credit for the good ones; and contrariwise is not responsible for the bad consequences of his good actions.”)
By swallowing Sidgwick’s terrible idea whole, says Anscombe, the consequentialists have elevated a moral temptation to the status of a moral philosophy.
Furthermore, because their philosophy demands prescience about consequences, but they can’t predict the future any better than the rest of us can, they cannot give us any actual practical ethical advice.
Instead, they give us the terminology in which we can better articulate our temptations to do shameful things, and they give us the predisposition to consent to the casuistry of other bad actors.
Is there a way to get back to moral oughts, or something like them, without divine law?
For example, a plant “needs” water, and you “ought to” see that the plant gets some if you want the plant to thrive.
But that “if” is where the problem lies, because “ought to” in the moral sense is supposed to somehow work without any “if” clause attached.
However, to the plant itself there doesn’t seem to be such a problem: it ought to pull in some water through its roots because otherwise it’s obviously doomed, and so pull water it does.
Is there some sense in which human beings “need” the virtues in order to thrive in the same sort of way that plants need water, in which case it would not be controversial that the fact of such a need generates (at least a rebuttable presumption of) an ought?
Even so, a modern moral philosopher could argue that we’ve just moved the problem rather than resolved it.
I need something to thrive, and I presumably ought therefore to pursue it if I want to thrive… there’s that “if” again.
(Some philosophers even try to attack divine-law theories on this ground, saying that even if you believe in divine law, its “oughts” have no force to compel action unless you also add “if you want to obey the divine law” to the end of them.)
What alternatives remain to the old-fashioned divine law model?
One possibility is a sort of natural law: divine law without the divinity.
Maybe such a law can be found in “natural religion”, or maybe in the norms of society (though when you see what kinds of norms societies have had, or take a close look at how nature legislates, maybe that’s not such a great idea).
Can you come up with laws on your own — legislate “for yourself” in a Kantean (or existentialist?) way?
Such things, Anscombe says, aren’t really laws; they’re at best a sort of stand-in for laws.
What about contractualism — the idea that moral law reflects an ancient or inevitable or mythical social contract?
Anscombe is skeptical, though says there is room for investigation in some of these paths.
Ah, but what about virtue ethics in the Aristotelian vein?
Anscombe considers this, and thinks it works, but only if you remember that Aristotle’s ethics predates the Christian change in moral terminology.
If you rewind the clock back that far, you go from the modern incoherent and mesmeric moral “ought” to the divine law’s commanded moral “ought” and then finally to an ethics in which the moral “ought” no longer makes an appearance.
So you aren’t going to solve the problem of making the moral ought make sense that way.
But that might be just fine: Anscombe thinks it’s time to put that problem on the shelf anyway.
But, says Anscombe, we are still a long way from being able to create a robust virtue ethics, as “philosophically there is a huge gap, at present unfillable as far as we are concerned, which needs to be filled by an account of human nature, human action, the type of characteristic a virtue is, and above all of human ‘flourishing.’ ”
But that daunting project seems to Anscombe more promising than the project of modern Anglophone moral philosophy circa 1958: to create ethical systems under which no act is so vile that some future hypothetical circumstance might retroactively justify it.
Although The Picket Line is mostly about tax resistance, I occasionally delve into other topics that interest me.
One of these is “virtue ethics.”
I’ve lately been doing a series of write-ups on individual virtues and posting them to the LessWrong site (LessWrong is a forum for the “rationalist” community).
Here’s what I've done so far:
I’ve got another project that will be taking a lot of my energy for the next several days, but I hope to continue this series of articles on virtues after that.
Julia Annas had written most of a book about virtue ethics when, she says, “it became clear… that I was writing the wrong book.” So she scrapped it in order “to start further back and get clear about virtue.” The book that resulted from this second attempt is Intelligent Virtue (Oxford University Press, 2011).
Intelligent Virtue clears up a lot of the fog around questions like “which characteristics are virtues, and why?” and “what is eudaimonia and what role is it meant to play in virtue-oriented ethics theories?”
It is a clear and well-organized account of the foundations of virtue ethics models.
Today I’ll try to summarize what stood out to me in Annas’s account of virtue:
What Is a Virtue?
According to Annas, a virtue is a feature or tendency or disposition of a person (not, that is, of an act or a non-person actor) that is:
persisting, reliable, and characteristic
active; developing in response to circumstances (not merely a passive disposition)
deep; central to who that person is
Virtues prompt virtuous actions, and those actions help to fortify that virtue, in a mutually-supporting way.
A virtue doesn’t give you a “decision procedure” or instruction manual for deciding what to do.
If you are skilled at a virtue, you will be able to perform that virtue well and to give an account for why you did it the way you did.
But this is different from having memorized a rulebook ahead of time and applying its directives to the situation.
Virtues tend to “cluster” in groups that mutually-support each other.
Annas gives the example of generosity, which requires a number of other virtues to do well.
You can’t just give willy-nilly, but you need to give in the right way to the right people, which requires other virtues (such as empathy, tact, benevolence, modesty).
One virtue that underlies all the others is phronesis (practical wisdom).
It supports the virtues in two ways: 1) each virtue requires phronesis in order to master it, and 2) if you have phronesis you will understand the importance of the virtues and how to develop them.
The aim of virtue is “to live well, to live a good life.”
Virtue and “Goodness”
All of the virtues support something we can call “goodness” — though Annas tries to remain agnostic as to what goodness consists of (she says that her account of the virtues is compatible with a variety of theories of goodness, from the hedonistic to the Platonic to the Christian).
Virtue is a sort of “commitment to goodness” while vice is (outside of fictional villains) not so much a commitment to badness as a failure to commit to goodness.
This reminded me of Hannah Arendt’s observation that the worst of evil is not done by wicked or evil people, but “by people who never made up their mind to be either bad or good.” In support of this, Annas considers the vice of the coward: Unlike the brave person looking back at her brave acts, the coward “cannot look back on his action in satisfaction, thinking that his cowardly act helped him in his overall aim to become a better coward.”
(But what about a cruel person, I wonder.
Are there no cruel people who come home from work thinking with satisfaction, “boy howdy, I thought I’d gotten about as cruel as I could get down at the prison, but I really turned things up a notch today!”)
Annas is skeptical that dispositions like “wittiness, tidiness, and affability” can be true virtues, since they seem to be things that are disconnected from goodness (you could be witty, tidy, or affable either as part of a commitment to goodness or without any such commitment); such things “can be exercised just as well viciously as virtuously.”
If all virtues aim toward “goodness” (however defined), you might wonder if maybe virtues derive from goodness and that we really should be looking at goodness as the foundational concept and… reinventing consequentialism instead.
Annas says that the way virtues connect to goodness does not lend itself to consequentialism.
“[W]hat makes a disposition a virtue is not the results it produces [emphasis mine] but, broadly speaking, the attitude of the person who has the virtue.”
Or, in another formulation: “exercising virtue is a commitment on the part of the virtuous person to goodness because it is goodness: goodness is not just an outcome.”
“Virtues are dispositions which are not only admirable but which we find inspiring and take as ideals to aspire to, precisely because of the commitment to goodness which they embody.”
Goodness and Eudaimonia
Annas says that it is a mistake to think of eudaimonia, as it is used in ancient ethical theories like Aristotle’s, as a precise, well-defined thing.
It’s more of a description of a thing.
Annas says that our aims in life tend to “nest”.
When we explain why we do something (brush our teeth) we do so by appealing to certain aims (to keep our teeth in good working order, to have pleasant breath, to avoid complications at the dentist), and we can then categorize those under broader aims (to be healthy, to be socially successful), and so on.
Annas thinks eudaimonia is a label for the outermost nesting; for the place we can stop explaining because it serves as the ultimate rational explanation for our behavior.
Why do I brush my teeth?
Ultimately, for eudaimonia.
We can try to better understand or specify eudaimonia, but we don’t need to start with a precise definition: we know it’s there, even if we don’t understand it all that well.
Eudaimonia is related to our telos; we aim for eudaimonia, and that determines our chosen telos.
The human telos, then, is not preexisting, but is something we discover or determine through examining the aims we choose.
By critiquing our aims and bringing them into alignment (and in alignment with our idea of what goodness consists of), we give ourselves an appropriate telos.
“The final end, then, is the indeterminate notion of what I am aiming at in my life as a whole.
And the role of ethical thinking is to get us to think more determinately about it, to do a better and more intelligently ordered job of what we are already doing anyway.”
Eudaimonia and Happiness
These days it’s common to fret about the word eudaimonia and how (or if) to translate it.
Annas thinks the old-fashioned translation of “happiness” is fine, as long as we’re careful to avoid certain modern uses of the word.
Happiness is not the same thing as “pleasure” and is not just the name of a certain sort of pleasant feeling.
It’s not just a matter of having your desires satisfied or feeling satisfied with how things are going in your life right now.
It’s neither wholly subjective nor wholly objective.
It has more to do with “the overall end you aim to achieve by living your life well” and as such it is both individual (it’s about your life specifically) and aspirational (you aren’t happy in a static way, but you aim at happiness).
“Happiness is at least in part activity”: it is a way-of-living.
How Do We Acquire Virtue?
A virtue can be best understood by looking at how it is acquired.
This “involves both the need to learn and the drive to aspire.”
The acquisition of a virtue is “not a once for all achievement” but involves “coming to understand what you are doing, doing it in a self-directed way, and trying to improve” so that your character develops and your understanding grows as you confront new challenges.
People do not first decide that a particular virtue is good, then decide to become virtuous in that way, and then develop a virtuous motivation.
Rather virtuous motivation develops alongside our understanding of the virtue, as “educated developments of our [preexisting] unformed motivations.”
“Becoming virtuous requires habituation and experience.”
We may begin to learn virtue by emulating or copying a role model, but learning true virtue demands that we aspire to understand the virtue.
This involves not just learning that you do something, but learning why you do something; this allows you to apply the virtue in novel circumstances rather than just performing a standardized routine.
As you learn this, you come to be able to articulate reasons for why you do what you do the way you do.
In this way a virtue is a lot like a skill.
When you begin to acquire a difficult skill (piano playing, say) you have to concentrate and you have to drill yourself on particular techniques in a pre-specified way.
But when you have acquired the skill, you don’t have to concentrate so much on the skill itself, but on how you are applying it in a particular situation.
Instead of struggling to do it competently, you can focus on doing it most skillfully or most beautifully or to meet certain circumstances.
As we improve our skill at a virtue in new and different contexts, we flesh-out our understanding of the virtue.
For example, if we are brave in a variety of situations (not just those requiring physical bravery in the face of a certain sort of threat) then we develop a broader understanding of what bravery consists of — what is common to all those responses that makes “bravery” a good description for them.
This expanded understanding in turn helps us to recognize and respond to new situations in which bravery is called for.
A virtuous person cares about being virtuous.
This is one way virtue is less like a productive skill, in which the point is the product rather than the process of making the product.
(Performative skills like dancing or acting are more similar to virtue in this way.)
That the being-virtuous is what matters brings to mind Aristotle’s distinction between a virtuous person (who is not tempted to vice because they care for virtue) and a person who is merely continent (who resists temptations to vice although they have not internalized an overriding love for virtue).
Both may do the same action in the same circumstance, but the first is virtuous while the second is merely exercising self-control.
Why Is Virtue Good for Us?
The enjoyment a virtuous person feels in exercising a virtue is analogous to the pleasant flow state of someone who is fluently practicing a skill, in which: 1) the activity is valued for itself, not just for its end-goal or product; and 2) there is a loss of self-consciousness during the activity.
Other aspects of flow include being “unhindered” (this does not mean without external obstacles, which can make the activity challenging in an interesting way, but without internal obstacles like reluctance or contrasting temptations); and being harmoniously-integrated (you are of one mind in the essence of what you are doing).
This also resembles Aristotle’s description in the Nicomachean Ethics of the pleasure that accompanies unimpeded activity.
Why Do People Fall Short?
If virtue is good for you and promotes happiness, why do people stop short of developing the virtues?
Annas suggests that this is in part because we love company, and there’s more of it to be found in mediocrity than in being outstanding.
When you separate from the pack in some particular virtue, say, honesty, you develop a sort of solidarity with other especially honest people, but you also lose some of the tolerance you used to have for people who exhibit commonplace dishonesty.
The companionship you feel towards your more abstract and dispersed community-of-the-honest is not as viscerally comforting as the more immediate community you used to feel with the people you typically encounter on a day-to-day basis.
Virtue can be lonely.
A Grotesque
This is the second time in recent years when I’ve read a book published before Donald Trump’s emergence as a politician in which he was used as a throwaway example of someone of obviously low character.
Here’s the quote from Intelligent Virtue:
We encourage children in schools, by means of posters, lessons, and books, to admire and aspire to be like some people and not others, and these are people whose characters are admirable and inspiring because of their commitment to goodness, regardless of whether in worldly terms they succeeded or failed, or were useful and/or agreeable to themselves or to other people.
This is why it would be grotesque to have posters in elementary schools depicting Donald Trump as a hero for the young, rather than people like King, Gandhi, and Mandela.